Immanuel Kant and Deontological Ethics

A Little Bit of Philosophy
14 May 202118:20

Summary

TLDRThis lecture introduces Immanuel Kant's deontological ethics, contrasting it with consequentialist theories like utilitarianism. Kant argues that moral obligation stems from rational laws, not outcomes. His categorical imperative demands treating rational beings as ends, never as means, emphasizing autonomy and respect for rational agency.

Takeaways

  • 📚 The lecture introduces deontological ethics, contrasting it with consequentialist theories like utilitarianism.
  • 🤔 Deontological theories assert that moral obligation is not determined by the consequences of actions but by the action's intrinsic nature or the agent's will.
  • 🧐 The lecture highlights various deontological theories including existentialism, stoicism, and the divine command theory.
  • 🎓 Immanuel Kant's moral theory, known as Kantianism, is the focus, which is rooted in his epistemological views.
  • 🧠 Kant's philosophy, German idealism, attempts to reconcile rationalism and empiricism by suggesting innate categories of the mind structure our understanding.
  • 🔄 Kant argues against the empiricist view that leads to skepticism, proposing instead that our minds actively organize sense data.
  • 🌐 Moral judgments for Kant are universal because they arise from practical reason, which is a law of pure reason applicable to all rational beings.
  • 📝 Kant's categorical imperative has three formulations: act only on principles that could be universally accepted, treat people as ends in themselves, and recognize the autonomy of rational agents.
  • 🚫 Lying is morally wrong for Kant because it uses people as a means to an end, not respecting their autonomy.
  • 🤝 The categorical imperative commands treating all rational beings, even those acting irrationally, with respect and as ends in themselves.
  • 🌟 Kant's moral theory is influential and continues to impact modern ethical debates, emphasizing the objectivity and absoluteness of morality.

Q & A

  • What is the main focus of this philosophy lecture?

    -The main focus of this philosophy lecture is on Immanuel Kant and his deontological ethics, specifically his moral theory known as continism.

  • What are the key differences between teleological and deontological ethics?

    -Teleological ethics focuses on the consequences of actions, defining moral obligation as achieving the best outcomes, such as pleasure or happiness. Deontological ethics, on the other hand, locates moral obligation in the intrinsic nature of the action or the will of the moral agent, independent of the consequences.

  • How does Kant's moral theory differ from moral egoism and hedonism?

    -Kant's moral theory differs from moral egoism and hedonism in that it does not view moral actions as being good because they lead to personal pleasure or happiness. Instead, Kant emphasizes the importance of acting according to the dictates of reason, which is universal and absolute.

  • What is the significance of Kant's attempt to synthesize rationalism and empiricism?

    -Kant's attempt to synthesize rationalism and empiricism is significant because it led to his development of transcendental idealism, which posits that our knowledge of things is shaped by both our sensory experiences and the innate structures of our minds. This synthesis influenced his moral theory, suggesting that moral knowledge is possible and objective.

  • What does Kant mean by 'practical reason'?

    -Kant refers to 'practical reason' as the aspect of reason that involves choice and will. It guides our actions and decisions, as opposed to 'pure reason' which is concerned with theoretical knowledge. Practical reason is what tells us what we ought to do.

  • What is the categorical imperative according to Kant?

    -The categorical imperative is Kant's moral principle that commands us to act only according to those maxims (rules of action) that we would be willing to make universal law. It has multiple formulations, emphasizing treating rational beings as ends in themselves and never merely as means to an end.

  • How does Kant define a 'good will'?

    -For Kant, a 'good will' is one that aligns with the dictates of reason. It is not good because of what it achieves or attains but is good in itself because it follows the moral law. A good will is the only thing that can be considered good without qualification.

  • What does Kant mean when he says rational agents should be treated as 'ends in themselves'?

    -Kant means that rational agents, because they possess autonomy and the capacity for reason, have intrinsic value and should be respected as such. They should not be used merely as a means to achieve some other end but should be treated with dignity and as an end in themselves.

  • How does Kant's moral theory relate to the concept of autonomy?

    -Kant's moral theory is deeply connected to the concept of autonomy, as it asserts that the moral worth of an action is determined by the agent's ability to act according to the principles of reason, which is the essence of autonomy. Moral agents are those who can act independently of external influences.

  • What are some examples of deontological theories other than Kant's continism?

    -Other deontological theories include existentialism, stoicism, and the divine command theory. Existentialism posits that moral obligation arises from free choices, stoicism locates it in the rational structure of the universe, and the divine command theory derives it from divine commands.

  • How does Kant's view on happiness differ from teleological theories?

    -Kant argues that happiness is not the ultimate goal or end that nature intends for us. Instead, nature has provided us with practical reason to guide our will, which often does not align with achieving happiness. For Kant, the pursuit of happiness is not the purpose of our rational agency.

Outlines

00:00

📚 Introduction to Deontological Ethics

This paragraph introduces the concept of deontological ethics, contrasting it with consequentialist theories like utilitarianism. It explains that deontological theories, such as Kant's, do not base moral obligation on the consequences of actions but rather on the intrinsic nature of the action itself or the will of the moral agent. The paragraph also provides an overview of other deontological theories like existentialism, stoicism, and the divine command theory, setting the stage for a deeper exploration of Kant's philosophy.

05:02

🧠 Kant's Epistemology and Moral Theory

The second paragraph delves into Immanuel Kant's background and his philosophical movement, German idealism. It discusses Kant's attempt to reconcile rationalism and empiricism by proposing the existence of innate categories that structure our understanding. This foundation leads to his moral theory, where moral judgments are seen as universal laws of practical reason. Kant argues that moral obligations are not relative but objective and binding on all rational beings, akin to mathematical truths.

10:03

🔑 The Categorical Imperative and Moral Autonomy

This section explains Kant's concept of the categorical imperative, which is the command of practical reason guiding our actions. It highlights that the categorical imperative has three formulations: treating rational agents as ends in themselves, deriving moral principles from the universalizability criterion, and recognizing the autonomy of rational beings. The paragraph emphasizes that rational agents are intrinsically valuable due to their capacity for autonomy, and moral actions should respect this value.

15:04

🗣️ The Implications of Kantian Ethics

The final paragraph discusses the practical implications of Kant's moral theory, particularly the absolute nature of the categorical imperative. It uses the example of lying to a potential murderer to illustrate the principle that one should never treat another rational agent as a means to an end. The paragraph concludes by summarizing Kant's moral theory as deontological, objective, and absolute, emphasizing the importance of acting according to the dictates of practical reason.

Mindmap

Keywords

💡Deontological Ethics

Deontological Ethics is a normative ethical theory that asserts that the morality of an action is determined by whether that action itself is right or wrong, rather than based on the consequences of the action. In the script, this concept is central to understanding Kant's moral philosophy, which argues that moral obligation is not based on the outcomes of actions but on the inherent rightness of the action itself.

💡Consequentialism

Consequentialism is the idea that the morality of an action is determined by its consequences. It is contrasted with deontological ethics in the script, where utilitarianism is presented as a form of consequentialism that seeks to maximize happiness or pleasure for the greatest number of people.

💡Utilitarianism

Utilitarianism is a consequentialist ethical theory that judges actions to be moral if they maximize overall happiness or pleasure. The script discusses Jeremy Bentham's version of utilitarianism and contrasts it with Kant's deontological ethics, highlighting the focus on outcomes over the nature of the action itself.

💡Moral Egoism

Moral Egoism is the idea that one should do what is in one's own self-interest. The script suggests that it might be considered the same as hedonism, focusing on individual pleasure or happiness, and contrasts it with utilitarianism, which seeks the greatest good for the greatest number.

💡Hedonism

Hedonism is the pursuit of pleasure as the highest good. In the script, it is discussed in the context of moral theories that focus on pleasure or happiness as the ultimate goal, with a note that philosophers often use 'pleasure' and 'happiness' interchangeably.

💡German Idealism

German Idealism is a philosophical movement that seeks to understand reality through the mind's categories of experience. Kant is identified as the founder of this movement in the script, and his moral theory is deeply influenced by his attempt to reconcile rationalism and empiricism within this framework.

💡Transcendental Idealism

Transcendental Idealism is Kant's philosophical view that our knowledge of things as they are in themselves is limited, and we can only know things as they appear to us. The script explains how Kant's moral theory is a consequence of this epistemological stance, suggesting that moral principles are derived from the rational structure of the mind.

💡Categorical Imperative

The Categorical Imperative is Kant's moral principle that one should act only according to those maxims that one wishes to become a universal law. It is a central concept in the script, illustrating how Kant believed moral actions should be based on principles that can be universally applied.

💡Autonomy

Autonomy in the context of the script refers to the capacity of rational beings to act according to the dictates of reason. Kant argues that autonomy is what makes rational agents intrinsically valuable, as they can act as if they are universal lawmakers, setting their own moral laws.

💡Heteronomy

Heteronomy is the opposite of autonomy and refers to being controlled by factors outside of one's will. The script uses this term to describe situations where individuals allow external factors to govern their actions, rather than acting according to their own rational principles.

💡Practical Reason

Practical Reason, as discussed in the script, is the aspect of reason that involves choice and action. It is distinguished from pure reason and is central to Kant's moral philosophy, which holds that moral actions are those that align with the demands of practical reason.

Highlights

Introduction to deontological ethics as opposed to consequentialism.

Explanation of how utilitarianism differs from moral egoism and hedonism by focusing on the greatest good for the greatest number.

Overview of deontological theories that reject the idea of moral obligation being determined by consequences.

Discussion on various deontological theories including existentialism, stoicism, and the divine command theory.

Emmanuel Kant's role as the founder of German idealism and his attempt to reconcile rationalism and empiricism.

Kant's epistemological project and its influence on his moral theory.

The concept of innate categories of the mind and their role in shaping our understanding of the world.

Kant's argument that moral obligations are universal and arise from practical reason.

The categorical imperative as the central principle of Kant's moral philosophy.

Kant's view that a good will is the only thing that is good in itself, not for its consequences.

Critique of teleological theories by Kant, emphasizing the role of practical reason over the pursuit of happiness.

The three basic moral propositions identified by Kant.

The first formulation of the categorical imperative: act only according to principles that can be universalized.

The second formulation of the categorical imperative: treat rational beings as ends in themselves, not as means to an end.

The intrinsic value of rational agents and the concept of autonomy.

The implications of Kant's moral theory on social interactions, such as the duty to tell the truth.

Kant's moral theory as a synthesis of empiricism and rationalism, leading to an objective and absolute morality.

Conclusion on the influence of Kant's deontological ethics in the modern period and beyond.

Transcripts

play00:00

welcome back to a little bit of

play00:02

philosophy

play00:03

this is philosophy 101 unit 4

play00:06

lecture 5 emmanuel kant and

play00:09

deontological ethics in our last video

play00:13

we explored the teleological branch of

play00:15

norman of ethics

play00:16

with an emphasis on jeremy bentham's

play00:19

version of utilitarianism

play00:21

what makes all three consequentialist

play00:23

theories similar

play00:25

is that they hold that moral obligation

play00:27

is defined as achieving the best

play00:29

consequences from our actions

play00:31

which is defined either as pleasure or

play00:33

happiness

play00:34

but of course as we noted previously

play00:37

clearly distinguishing between the

play00:38

concepts of pleasure and happiness

play00:40

can be a little tricky and many

play00:42

philosophers have

play00:44

used the terms almost interchangeably

play00:47

thus it might be

play00:48

argued that moral egoism and hedonism

play00:51

are really just the same

play00:52

thing what distinguishes utilitarianism

play00:56

from the other two

play00:57

is its insistence that the greatest

play00:59

happiness or pleasure

play01:00

should be sought for the greatest number

play01:02

of people not

play01:04

just for the individual moral agent

play01:07

in this video we'll turn to the

play01:10

deontological branch of normative ethics

play01:12

theories that fall under this heading

play01:14

all reject the idea that moral

play01:16

obligation

play01:17

is determined by the consequences of our

play01:19

actions

play01:20

instead deontological theories locate

play01:23

moral obligation

play01:25

either in some intrinsic feature of the

play01:27

action

play01:28

or the will of the immoral agent there

play01:31

are many different

play01:32

moral theories that fall under this

play01:34

heading but

play01:35

existentialism stoicism continuism

play01:38

and the divine command theory are among

play01:41

the more popular

play01:42

deontological types the divine command

play01:45

theory

play01:45

holds that moral obligation is derived

play01:48

from the fact

play01:49

that god has given a command while

play01:51

existentialism holds that moral

play01:53

obligation

play01:54

is created through our radically free

play01:56

choices

play01:58

alternatively stoicism locates moral

play02:00

obligation in the

play02:01

cosmic lagos or rational structure

play02:05

of the universe all these theories are

play02:08

fascinating

play02:09

and deserve a video of their own but

play02:11

today

play02:12

we'll be focusing on the moral theory of

play02:14

immanuel kant

play02:15

conveniently known simply as continuism

play02:19

now emmanuel kant is the founder

play02:22

of a philosophical movement known as

play02:25

german idealism

play02:26

which was popular in the 18th and 19th

play02:29

centuries which

play02:30

at heart sought to distinguish our

play02:33

knowledge of things

play02:34

in themselves versus how things appear

play02:37

to us to be

play02:39

the movement grows out of kant's attempt

play02:41

to synthesize the two

play02:43

major competing epistemological theories

play02:45

of the modern period

play02:47

rationalism and empiricism

play02:50

as we explored in our videos on the

play02:52

subject of epistemology

play02:54

the early modern or enlightenment period

play02:56

was in large part shaped by the desire

play02:59

to respond to the intellectual chaos

play03:02

and skepticism that grew out of the

play03:04

radical social and intellectual

play03:06

transformations of the renaissance

play03:09

the cartesian school held that knowledge

play03:11

was dependent

play03:12

on the existence of certain innate

play03:14

cognitions that form a secure foundation

play03:17

of a priori

play03:18

ideas which could be used to justify our

play03:22

posteriori ideas arising from sensory

play03:24

experience

play03:26

on the other hand the empirical

play03:28

tradition arising from the works of john

play03:30

locke

play03:31

and expanded on later by david hume held

play03:34

that there were no innate ideas

play03:36

and that all knowledge that we would

play03:38

ever be able to attain

play03:41

must be based on direct sensory

play03:43

perception

play03:44

or the relationships that exist between

play03:47

the ideas that we derive

play03:48

from direct sensory experience now in

play03:51

our last video

play03:52

we saw that the utilitarian moral theory

play03:55

of jeremy bentham and john stuart mill

play03:57

was a direct response to the growing

play04:00

influence of the empirical theory of

play04:02

knowledge

play04:03

emmanuel kant a contemporary of bentham

play04:06

would develop an alternative moral

play04:08

theory which arose from his attempt to

play04:10

find

play04:11

a middle ground between the rationalist

play04:14

and

play04:14

empirical approaches to knowledge now

play04:17

kant agreed with the

play04:19

empiricists rejection of innate ideas

play04:22

but he was horrified by hume's argument

play04:24

that empiricism

play04:25

would inevitably lead to skepticism

play04:28

regarding sensory observations in other

play04:30

words

play04:31

there's no such thing as scientific

play04:33

knowledge

play04:34

his solution was to argue that while

play04:36

there were no

play04:37

innate ideas there were innate

play04:40

categories which form the structure

play04:42

of any rational mind so for kant

play04:46

the mind is not passively receiving

play04:48

ideas from

play04:49

external objects but rather our sense

play04:53

data

play04:53

is being processed or organized by the

play04:56

innate categories of the mind

play04:59

creating what he called judgments or

play05:02

thoughts of course this still leaves a

play05:04

gap

play05:05

between how things actually are in the

play05:08

world

play05:08

and how we understand them to be but

play05:11

kant argued that the objective nature of

play05:13

the categories of the mind

play05:15

meant that knowledge was possible

play05:18

including

play05:19

moral knowledge kant's theory of

play05:22

knowledge

play05:23

is going to shape his entire moral

play05:26

theory

play05:27

for example when we examine our moral

play05:30

judgments our moral thoughts

play05:32

we find that they are centered in our

play05:34

understanding that

play05:35

obligation or oughtness is really

play05:38

nothing other

play05:39

than the recognition of a law of pure

play05:42

practical reason

play05:44

given that obligation arises from a

play05:47

rational law

play05:49

it follows that it must be universal in

play05:51

its scope it must be

play05:52

equally binding on any being capable

play05:56

of conceiving an obligation this is what

play05:59

we learned earlier

play06:00

as the universalizability criterion of

play06:03

an acceptable moral principle

play06:06

which is the central point moral

play06:07

objectivists make in arguing against

play06:10

relativism if moral obligations

play06:13

are relative then they can't be equally

play06:16

binding

play06:17

on all moral agents only those who are

play06:20

part of the group to whom the moral

play06:22

principle is relative

play06:24

imagine that you had two groups of

play06:26

people and one asserted that

play06:28

two plus two equals four while the other

play06:30

asserted that two plus two is five

play06:33

if the rules of reason were relative

play06:36

then they might both be

play06:37

right but if the rules of reason are

play06:40

objective

play06:42

then one of these groups has to be wrong

play06:45

kant's argument is that since morality

play06:48

like arithmetic

play06:49

is derived from the rules of reason then

play06:52

the rules of morality will be universal

play06:56

as well now the difference

play07:00

between arithmetic and morality for kant

play07:03

is that the former is derived from pure

play07:05

reason and the latter from

play07:07

practical reason which just means that

play07:10

it involves choice

play07:12

that means that the will of the moral

play07:14

agent

play07:15

is essential in acting on what reason

play07:18

demands

play07:19

we could know what reason tells us is

play07:21

good but we still have to act upon it

play07:25

we have to bring our will to act in line

play07:29

with the dictates of reason

play07:31

if our will aligns with the good it can

play07:33

be described as a

play07:35

good will and for kant

play07:38

this is the only thing that can be

play07:40

properly described as

play07:42

good in itself it's not good because

play07:45

it's aimed at achieving some

play07:47

and or attaining something else it is

play07:50

good

play07:50

solely because it is aligned with the

play07:53

dictates of reason

play07:55

or as he puts it

play07:59

a good will is good not because of what

play08:02

it performs or what it affects

play08:05

not by its aptness for the attainment of

play08:07

some proposed end

play08:09

but simply in virtue of the volition

play08:14

this is precisely where teleological

play08:17

theories

play08:18

fail according to kant egoists hedonists

play08:21

even utilitarians are attempting to will

play08:24

some particular

play08:25

consequence be it pleasure or happiness

play08:27

or happiness for the greatest number

play08:29

but he argues this doesn't match up with

play08:32

what we discover

play08:33

about the world instead he argues that

play08:37

when we examine the structure of nature

play08:40

we discover it contains perfect

play08:42

adaptations

play08:43

to ends so if happiness was what nature

play08:47

had intended for us

play08:48

it would have provided us with an

play08:50

instinctive guide to happiness

play08:53

but what nature has given us is

play08:55

practical reason to guide our will

play08:58

not instinctive behavior aimed at

play09:00

happiness

play09:01

and the dictates of practical reason

play09:03

don't always make us happy

play09:05

thus we are designed to be rational

play09:09

agents

play09:10

not happiness seeking agents

play09:13

that of course doesn't make happiness or

play09:15

pleasure bad

play09:16

it just means that those ends those

play09:19

consequences

play09:20

are not what we are designed to seek by

play09:24

nature

play09:25

now with this in mind kant identifies

play09:28

three basic moral propositions

play09:32

first rightness is determined by our

play09:36

recognition

play09:37

of an obligation to act in a certain way

play09:40

that is we feel the sting of oughtness

play09:43

because we have a duty to do something

play09:46

second

play09:47

the rightness of the obligation is

play09:50

derived from the principle of practical

play09:52

reason

play09:53

that gives that obligation in other

play09:56

words

play09:57

the obligation arises from

play10:00

our awareness of the principle

play10:03

that is part of the rational structure

play10:05

of our mind

play10:07

so we can understand the idea of duty or

play10:10

obligation

play10:11

as the motivation we feel to obey

play10:14

the laws of reason and in the case of

play10:17

morality

play10:18

the laws of practical reason again to

play10:21

use the example of

play10:22

arithmetic when i'm confronted with the

play10:25

question

play10:25

what's the solution to two plus two

play10:28

reason

play10:28

tells me that the answer is four of

play10:32

course

play10:32

i'm free to answer five or square

play10:36

or even fish if i want to but to do so

play10:39

would be to act

play10:40

contrary to what i know is the correct

play10:42

answer

play10:44

the same is true in the realm of

play10:46

practical reason

play10:47

when i ask what should i do

play10:50

the answer already lies in the very

play10:53

structure

play10:53

of my rational mind the answer is

play10:57

contained

play10:57

in the categorical imperative

play11:01

now the word imperative is just a fancy

play11:03

philosophical word for command

play11:05

so kant is saying that when it comes to

play11:08

action

play11:09

practical reason which is part of the

play11:12

structure of our mind

play11:14

tells us what we ought to do if i'm

play11:17

hungry

play11:17

it tells me to eat if i'm tired it tells

play11:19

me to sleep

play11:20

but these commands are not good in

play11:23

themselves

play11:24

they're good for the sake of something

play11:25

else they would be examples of what he

play11:27

calls

play11:28

hypothetical commands commands that are

play11:30

aimed at achieving

play11:31

something other than themselves some and

play11:34

if i'm hungry i should eat if i'm tired

play11:37

i should sleep

play11:38

but when it comes to my interaction with

play11:41

other rational beings

play11:43

reason gives us an absolute command

play11:46

a categorical imperative

play11:49

it is not good because it secures some

play11:52

end like happiness or pleasure

play11:55

it is something good in itself

play11:59

now when we think about the categorical

play12:01

command of practical reason

play12:03

we find that it contains three distinct

play12:06

formulations or

play12:08

has at least three different dimensions

play12:11

the first tells us what kind of

play12:13

principle we should choose to follow

play12:16

regarding our interactions with other

play12:18

rational agents

play12:20

this first formulation of the

play12:22

categorical imperative tells us

play12:24

that the principle we should choose to

play12:26

follow

play12:27

is one that we would want everyone else

play12:30

to choose to follow

play12:31

as well since all moral agents are

play12:34

rational agents alike

play12:36

we should only adhere to a principle

play12:38

that would be

play12:39

equally binding on all of us

play12:42

and what is it that reason tells us that

play12:45

such a principle would be

play12:47

it tells us that we should always act

play12:50

toward other rational agents

play12:52

as if they were an end in themselves

play12:55

not means by which we can achieve some

play12:58

other end

play12:59

persons that is beings with a rational

play13:02

mind

play13:02

are not objects they're not tools

play13:05

they're not

play13:06

instruments they are intrinsically

play13:09

valuable

play13:10

and therefore worthy of respect equal to

play13:13

oneself

play13:15

but why what makes a rational agent

play13:19

intrinsically valuable the answer lies

play13:23

in the third dimension of the

play13:24

categorical imperative

play13:26

because in every rational agent

play13:29

there is a will that has the ability to

play13:32

order its actions

play13:34

as if it were the universal lawmaker

play13:38

the intrinsic value of a rational being

play13:41

lies in their autonomy their

play13:45

ability to act in accordance with the

play13:48

dictates of reason

play13:49

of course as kant makes clear just

play13:52

because we have the capacity to act

play13:54

according to the dictates of reason

play13:56

doesn't mean that we will do so we very

play13:59

often act

play14:00

heteronomously that is we allow

play14:02

ourselves to be controlled

play14:04

in ways that are beyond our direct

play14:07

will we allow ourselves to be ruled by

play14:10

others that's what heteronomy the

play14:13

opposite of autonomy means

play14:16

but this fact that we often act

play14:18

heteronomously

play14:19

is not a defective reason it's a defect

play14:22

of our will

play14:23

to do that which we as rational agents

play14:27

know we ought to do now the consequences

play14:31

of cons moral theory can be a little

play14:33

startling to our common feelings about

play14:36

social interaction if someone asks me

play14:39

how i feel about their new hat the

play14:42

categorical imperative

play14:44

tells me that i ought to tell the truth

play14:47

being honest might be a breach of

play14:49

etiquette

play14:50

but since they are a rational agent i

play14:53

should never lie to them

play14:55

to do so would be to violate their

play14:58

autonomy

play14:59

to treat them not as an end in

play15:01

themselves but rather as a means to

play15:03

some other and now of course the

play15:06

categorical imperative doesn't compel me

play15:08

to answer

play15:09

but if i choose to answer

play15:13

it should be truthful even more

play15:16

startling

play15:16

is the case of the potential murderer

play15:18

who demands to know

play15:20

where you're hiding someone that they

play15:22

intend to kill

play15:24

even the person threatening murder is a

play15:27

rational agent

play15:28

even though they aren't necessarily

play15:30

acting according to the categorical

play15:31

imperative

play15:32

but that doesn't change the fact that

play15:35

you're forbidden to lie

play15:37

now you can refuse to answer or you

play15:40

could

play15:40

attempt to constrain the murderer or

play15:44

you could reason with them about why

play15:46

they're acting

play15:47

irrationally but you cannot lie to them

play15:51

because doing so would be to treat them

play15:54

as a means to an end

play15:57

now the case of lying is just one

play16:00

example

play16:01

of how the categorical imperative is an

play16:04

absolute command

play16:05

of practical reason similar outcomes

play16:08

would follow from

play16:09

any interaction between rational agents

play16:13

the categorical imperative commands us

play16:15

to

play16:16

always treat other rational agents

play16:19

including ourselves as ends in

play16:22

themselves

play16:23

never as a means to some other

play16:26

end there is so much more

play16:30

we could say about kant's moral theory

play16:32

but as always

play16:33

we're limited by time suffice it to say

play16:37

that this approach to morality

play16:39

is clearly deontological since the

play16:42

consequences of our actions are

play16:43

irrelevant in determining what we ought

play16:46

to do

play16:47

further kant's theory is a consequence

play16:50

of his epistemological project to find

play16:52

some

play16:53

middle ground between empiricism and

play16:56

rationalism the kantian synthesis known

play16:59

as

play17:00

transcendental idealism leads us to

play17:03

recognize

play17:04

that only a person who always chooses

play17:07

according to reason can be considered

play17:10

good

play17:10

in themselves since practical reason

play17:13

is the only proper guide to the will and

play17:16

since it forms the structure of the

play17:18

rational mind

play17:19

morality for kant will be both objective

play17:23

and absolute and finally

play17:27

what practical reason dictates is the

play17:29

categorical

play17:30

imperative which tells us that we should

play17:32

always choose a moral principle

play17:34

that is universalizable that we should

play17:37

always treat rational agents including

play17:39

ourselves

play17:40

as ends and never as tools or

play17:42

instruments to achieve some other

play17:44

end and that re the reason that rational

play17:48

agents are intrinsically valuable

play17:50

is that by nature all rational agents

play17:53

have the ability to act autonomously

play17:57

next to utilitarianism continism is the

play18:00

most

play18:01

influential moral theory to develop in

play18:03

the modern period

play18:04

and its influence continues down to the

play18:07

present

play18:08

in the great debate in normative ethics

play18:11

that's all for now be sure to come back

play18:14

again as we continue to explore

play18:16

a little bit of philosophy

Rate This

5.0 / 5 (0 votes)

الوسوم ذات الصلة
Philosophy 101Deontological EthicsImmanuel KantMoral TheoryCategorical ImperativeRationalism vs EmpiricismMoral ObligationPractical ReasonAutonomyEthics Debate
هل تحتاج إلى تلخيص باللغة الإنجليزية؟