Introducing Deontological/Kantian Ethics

Wes McMichael
15 Jun 202214:48

Summary

TLDRThis script discusses deontological ethics, also known as Kantian ethics, focusing on the philosopher Immanuel Kant's belief in ethical rules derived from reason rather than consequences. It contrasts deontological ethics with consequentialism and virtue ethics, emphasizing the importance of adhering to moral principles regardless of outcomes. The script introduces Kant's categorical imperative, explaining how it guides ethical decision-making through the universal law of nature and the humanity as an end formula, ensuring actions are universally permissible and respect human dignity.

Takeaways

  • πŸ“š The video discusses the second of the 'big three' ethical theories, deontological ethics, also known as Kantian ethics, which is named after the philosopher Immanuel Kant.
  • πŸ€” Deontological ethics asserts that the morality of an action is determined by whether it adheres to a rule or principle, rather than the consequences of the action.
  • 🚫 The theory emphasizes that some acts are inherently wrong, no matter the potential benefits, because they violate moral rules, such as killing the innocent.
  • πŸ€“ Consequences do matter in deontological ethics but are not the sole determinant of right or wrong; they can be considered after establishing permissibility based on rules.
  • πŸ“– Elizabeth Anscombe's quote is highlighted, emphasizing that choosing to kill the innocent as a means to an end is always wrong, regardless of the context or potential outcomes.
  • 🧐 The source of moral rules in deontological ethics is explored, with the traditional answers being divine commands or reason, with Kant advocating for the latter.
  • πŸ”„ Disagreements within and between religions about moral rules suggest that divine command theory may not provide a clear or universally accepted set of ethical rules.
  • πŸ€” Kant's view introduces a distinction between hypothetical and categorical imperatives, with the former being goal-dependent and the latter being universally applicable.
  • 🌐 The 'Universal Law of Nature' formula is presented as a way to test whether an action's maxim can be logically universalized without contradiction.
  • πŸ§‘β€πŸ€β€πŸ§‘ The 'Humanity as an End' formula is mentioned as another formulation of the categorical imperative, which will be discussed in more detail in a subsequent video.

Q & A

  • What are the 'big three' ethical theories mentioned in the script?

    -The 'big three' ethical theories mentioned in the script are consequentialism, deontological ethics (also known as Kantian ethics), and virtue ethics.

  • Who is Immanuel Kant and why is deontological ethics also called Kantian ethics?

    -Immanuel Kant is a philosopher credited for organizing the way of thinking known as deontological ethics. It is also called Kantian ethics because Kant is considered the primary figure who developed and systematized this ethical theory.

  • What is the main distinction between deontological ethics and consequentialism?

    -Deontological ethics focuses on the inherent rightness or wrongness of actions based on rules or principles, regardless of their consequences. Consequentialism, on the other hand, judges the morality of an action based on the goodness or badness of its consequences.

  • How do consequences factor into deontological ethics?

    -In deontological ethics, consequences do matter but they do not solely determine what is right or wrong. An action's permissibility is primarily based on adherence to moral rules or principles, and consequences can be considered after the action's permissibility is established.

  • What is the significance of Elizabeth Anscombe's statement regarding killing the innocent?

    -Elizabeth Anscombe's statement emphasizes that certain actions, such as killing the innocent, are always wrong regardless of the potential benefits or outcomes. This highlights the deontological view that some moral rules are absolute and should not be violated.

  • What are the two traditional sources of moral rules according to the script?

    -The two traditional sources of moral rules mentioned in the script are divine commands from God and reason, as proposed by Immanuel Kant.

  • What is the difference between hypothetical and categorical imperatives in Kantian ethics?

    -Hypothetical imperatives provide guidance on how to achieve a goal one already has, while categorical imperatives state what one should do without any conditions, applying universally to all rational beings.

  • What does the universal law of nature formula state?

    -The universal law of nature formula states that one should 'act only in accordance with that maxim through which you can at the same time will that it become a universal law.' It is a test to determine if an action's maxim can be logically universalized without contradiction.

  • What is the humanity as an end formula and what does it imply?

    -The humanity as an end formula states that one should 'act so that you treat humanity whether in your own person or in that of another always as an end and never as a means only.' It implies that individuals should always be treated with respect and never merely as a means to an end.

  • How does Kant's categorical imperative relate to the concept of universalizability?

    -Kant's categorical imperative is connected to universalizability through the process of testing whether an action's maxim can be consistently applied universally. If an action's maxim leads to a logical contradiction when universally applied, it is morally impermissible.

Outlines

00:00

πŸ“š Introduction to Deontological Ethics

This paragraph introduces deontological ethics, also known as Kantian ethics, named after the philosopher Immanuel Kant who is credited with organizing this ethical theory. Deontological ethics is one of the 'big three' ethical theories, alongside consequentialism and virtue ethics. It posits that the morality of an act is determined by whether it adheres to a rule or principle, rather than the consequences of the act. Even if the outcomes are good, acts that violate ethical rules are considered wrong. The paragraph also touches on the difficulty in understanding Kant's work and the importance of considering both rules and consequences in ethical decision-making.

05:01

πŸ“– Understanding Hypothetical and Categorical Imperatives

This paragraph delves into the concepts of hypothetical and categorical imperatives as part of deontological ethics. Hypothetical imperatives are conditional commands that depend on a pre-existing goal, guiding actions to achieve that goal. In contrast, categorical imperatives are universal and apply to all rational beings regardless of personal goals. The paragraph explains that while hypothetical imperatives are goal-dependent, categorical imperatives are not and are derived from reason alone. Kant's view on ethics is that moral rules can be discovered through reason, not just divine commands, and the paragraph sets the stage for exploring Kant's formulations of the categorical imperative.

10:02

πŸ” The Universal Law of Nature Formula

This paragraph focuses on the 'Universal Law of Nature' formula of the categorical imperative, which is a key component of Kantian ethics. It explains that one should only act according to a maxim (a general principle or rule) if they can logically will that it becomes a universal law. The paragraph outlines a procedure for testing the morality of an action: formulate the action into a maxim and then determine if it can be universally applied without logical contradiction. Examples such as cheating and lying are used to illustrate how this formula works, showing that actions that cannot be universally applied without contradiction are morally impermissible according to the Universal Law of Nature.

Mindmap

Keywords

πŸ’‘Deontological Ethics

Deontological ethics, also known as Kantian ethics, is a normative ethical theory that emphasizes duty and moral rules. It is named after Immanuel Kant, who is credited with organizing this way of thinking. In the video, deontological ethics is described as a rule-based ethical theory where the morality of an action is determined by whether it adheres to a moral rule or principle, rather than the consequences of the action.

πŸ’‘Consequentialism

Consequentialism is an ethical theory that judges the morality of an action based on the goodness or badness of its consequences. Although the video's main focus is on deontological ethics, consequentialism is mentioned as one of the 'big three' ethical theories, contrasting with deontological ethics by suggesting that the rightness or wrongness of an action is determined by its outcomes.

πŸ’‘Virtue Ethics

Virtue ethics is another of the 'big three' ethical theories mentioned in the video. It focuses on the character of the moral agent, emphasizing virtues such as courage, honesty, and wisdom. While not the main focus of the video, virtue ethics is contrasted with deontological ethics to highlight different ethical approaches.

πŸ’‘Immanuel Kant

Immanuel Kant is a German philosopher who is central to the discussion in the video. He is known for his work on ethics, particularly deontological ethics, and is credited with organizing the principles that define this ethical theory. The video script mentions Kant as a difficult philosopher to understand, indicating his significant but complex contribution to ethical philosophy.

πŸ’‘Rule-Based Ethical Theory

A rule-based ethical theory, as discussed in the video, is one where morality is determined by adherence to a set of rules or principles, rather than the consequences of actions. Deontological ethics is presented as an example of a rule-based theory, where certain acts are considered right or wrong based on whether they follow moral rules, regardless of the outcome.

πŸ’‘Categorical Imperative

The categorical imperative is a key concept in Kantian ethics, introduced in the video as a way to determine moral rules through reason. It is a principle that commands action according to reason, without condition. The video explains that Kant provides different formulations of the categorical imperative, which are used to derive moral laws.

πŸ’‘Hypothetical Imperatives

Hypothetical imperatives are mentioned in the video as a type of command that depends on a specific goal or condition. They are conditional and suggest a course of action based on a desired outcome. For example, 'if you want to be a doctor, you should go to medical school.' These are contrasted with categorical imperatives, which are unconditional and apply universally.

πŸ’‘Divine Commands

Divine commands refer to the idea that moral rules come from a divine source, such as God. In the video, this concept is discussed as one traditional answer to the question of where moral rules come from. However, it is also noted that disagreements within and between religions can complicate this theory.

πŸ’‘Moral Rules

Moral rules are principles that guide ethical behavior. In the context of the video, moral rules are derived from reason in deontological ethics, as opposed to divine commands or other sources. The video discusses how these rules are foundational to determining what actions are right or wrong.

πŸ’‘Universal Law of Nature

The universal law of nature is one of Kant's formulations of the categorical imperative. It is presented in the video as a test for moral maxims: act only according to the maxim that you can will to become a universal law. This formula is used to determine whether an action is morally permissible by considering if it could be a universal principle without contradiction.

πŸ’‘Humanity as an End

Humanity as an end is another formulation of the categorical imperative mentioned in the video. It states that one should act in such a way that humanity is treated as an end in itself, never merely as a means. This concept emphasizes the inherent dignity and value of every person, which should not be violated for the sake of some other goal or purpose.

Highlights

Introduction to deontological ethics as one of the 'big three' ethical theories alongside consequentialism and virtue ethics.

Deontological ethics is also known as Kantian ethics, named after the philosopher Immanuel Kant.

Kant is credited for organizing the deontological way of thinking, which is rule-based rather than consequences-based.

Acts are judged right or wrong based on adherence to ethical rules or principles, not just their consequences.

Consequences do matter in deontological ethics but are not the sole determinant of morality.

Elizabeth Anscombe's quote emphasizes that killing the innocent is always wrong, regardless of the ends.

Deontological ethics asserts that some acts are intrinsically wrong, such as torturing a baby, regardless of potential benefits.

The source of moral rules is a central question in deontological ethics, with divine commands and reason as traditional answers.

Kant believed ethical rules could be derived through reason alone, without divine commands.

Disagreements within and between religions pose a challenge to divine command theory as a source of moral rules.

Kant's focus on reason introduces the concept of hypothetical and categorical imperatives in moral decision-making.

Hypothetical imperatives are conditional and depend on personal goals, unlike categorical imperatives.

Categorical imperatives are universal and apply to all rational beings, setting the goals and means of morality.

Kant provides five formulations for the categorical imperative, with two being discussed: the universal law of nature and humanity as an end.

The universal law of nature formula states to act only according to maxims that could be willed as universal laws.

The humanity as an end formula asserts that one should always treat humanity as an end, never as a means.

The procedure for applying the universal law of nature involves formulating a maxim and testing its universality for logical consistency.

Examples are given to illustrate the process of testing maxims for universality, such as cheating on a final paper.

The concept of lying is used to demonstrate the logical inconsistency of universalizing a maxim that undermines trust.

Transcripts

play00:00

this is the second of what i call the

play00:02

big three ethical theory so we have

play00:04

consequentialism deontological ethics

play00:07

also called kantian ethics and you'll

play00:09

hear me say kantian as much as

play00:11

deontological kantian immanuel kant uh

play00:14

because he's kind of credited for

play00:16

organizing this way of thinking so

play00:17

deontological thinking and kantian

play00:20

ethics uh referred to the same thing and

play00:23

then there's gonna be virtue ethics

play00:24

which is the third of the big three and

play00:26

then we'll talk about social contract to

play00:27

feminist ethics and that kind of stuff

play00:29

as well all right so like i said it's

play00:31

one of the more popular ethical theories

play00:33

among philosophers and non-philosophers

play00:35

uh like i said it's just as commonly

play00:37

referred to as kantian ethics after the

play00:39

philosopher immanuel kant who's very

play00:41

hard to understand so my apologies uh

play00:43

for the reading it's he's just a very

play00:45

hard person to figure out a lot of

play00:48

german students will actually read him

play00:49

in english to get the just the

play00:52

translation uh to understand him better

play00:56

the idea is that some acts no matter how

play00:59

good the consequences are simply wrong

play01:02

because they violate a rule or principle

play01:05

of ethics and some acts no matter how

play01:07

bad the consequences are simply right

play01:09

because they adhere to the right rule or

play01:12

principle of ethics so a lot of times

play01:14

you'll hear this referred to as a

play01:16

rule-based ethical theory versus a

play01:19

consequences based do consequences

play01:21

matter in deontological ethics of course

play01:24

they do

play01:25

so what we do in the

play01:28

in kantian or deontological ethics is we

play01:31

find out whether or not we're permitted

play01:33

to do something and we might be

play01:35

permitted to do more than one thing and

play01:37

then we can look at the consequences of

play01:39

that so consequences absolutely do

play01:41

matter but they don't determine what is

play01:43

right or wrong alone right you can

play01:46

factor them in but they are not the

play01:48

deciding factors because you are never

play01:51

permitted to do something

play01:54

that is atrocious so

play01:57

elizabeth anscum philosopher famously

play02:00

said for men to choose to kill the

play02:02

innocent as a means to their ends is

play02:04

always murder and she was actually

play02:06

referring to that um in the context

play02:10

at her time of nuclear war and that was

play02:14

that was right before the bombing of

play02:16

hiroshima and nagasaki and she was

play02:18

saying that you cannot justify that for

play02:20

men to choose to kill the innocent as a

play02:23

means to their ends is always murder

play02:24

always wrong

play02:26

we could say that no matter how much

play02:27

good could come of it no matter how

play02:29

people it might

play02:30

save you can't poke a baby in the eye

play02:32

with a red hot fire poker just to hear a

play02:34

sizzle or boiling a baby alive is simply

play02:36

wrong it does not matter what the

play02:39

consequences are for some things some

play02:41

things are wrong because they violate a

play02:44

moral rule but you might be wondering

play02:47

from whence cometh the rules if you're a

play02:50

16th century

play02:51

you might be wondering that or in other

play02:53

words you might wonder where do these

play02:54

rules come from and there's been two

play02:56

traditional answers we

play02:58

have talked about one already god

play03:00

through divine commands we've seen what

play03:02

the problems are through that and then

play03:05

uh reason and that's what

play03:08

kant said we can find them through

play03:09

reason not that he didn't accept god he

play03:11

did he believed in god

play03:14

but he thought that we could get the

play03:16

ethical rules through our reason alone

play03:19

and we didn't need commands

play03:23

we talked about already so i won't go

play03:25

over them again the problems with

play03:27

divine command theory but remember there

play03:30

was one issue that i said that was

play03:33

that i told you uh well maybe this isn't

play03:35

much of a problem i said look

play03:38

different people within a religion

play03:40

disagree on what's right or wrong so i

play03:42

used to go to a church when i was

play03:44

religious that had been doing same-sex

play03:46

unions since the 70s i had gone to

play03:49

another church who

play03:51

to this day believes that it's immoral

play03:54

for uh homosexuals to

play03:56

marry or to be together or to love each

play03:58

other or anything like that and so and

play04:00

those were two christians because i was

play04:02

a christian those were two christian

play04:04

religions right and so there's

play04:05

disagreements within religions there's

play04:07

disagreements outside of religions you

play04:09

know muslims disagree with christians

play04:11

and jews jews disagree jews and muslims

play04:13

disagree with christians about the

play04:14

nature of the godhead all those kind of

play04:16

things right

play04:17

and so um you have these disagreements

play04:20

and i told you well that wasn't much of

play04:21

a problem for divine command theory but

play04:23

they could be a problem if we're saying

play04:25

the rules come from a god because then

play04:27

we just don't know what they are and we

play04:29

need to know what they are to know what

play04:31

to do in the case of the ontological

play04:33

rule-based ethics right so our focus is

play04:36

going to be on this idea of reason then

play04:39

how reason can

play04:41

generate the rules of morality uh before

play04:44

i do that i have to

play04:45

because i'm going to explain kant's view

play04:47

of this i have to make a distinction

play04:49

that he makes between what we call

play04:50

hypothetical and categorical imperatives

play04:53

so you might remember the word

play04:55

imperative from your

play04:57

elementary school and

play04:59

hopefully not high school but whenever

play05:01

you learn grammar

play05:03

you learned about imperative so if i

play05:05

were to say open the door close the door

play05:07

do your homework those are commands

play05:09

those are what we call imperatives so

play05:11

we're talking about two types of

play05:13

imperative two types of commands here

play05:15

we're talking about hypothetical and you

play05:17

might have heard that word before

play05:18

hypothetical you know it's like i'm

play05:20

gonna give you a hypothetical situation

play05:23

imagine that we could fly you know uh

play05:25

and then categorical um and those are

play05:28

universal kind of things and so

play05:30

kant makes these distinctions between

play05:32

hypothetical and categorical

play05:34

both of these ideas are meant to

play05:36

describe the role of reason in making a

play05:38

decision one holds that reason is

play05:41

instrumental i mean that means it can be

play05:43

used as an instrument to help us achieve

play05:45

our goals but it cannot set the goals so

play05:48

something like if you want to be a

play05:50

doctor then you should go to medical

play05:52

school you should go to medical school

play05:54

doesn't apply unless i want to be a

play05:56

doctor because why would i go to medical

play05:58

school otherwise right maybe i just want

play05:59

to learn something or whatever but they

play06:01

should part doesn't really apply and so

play06:03

that's the hypothetical the other

play06:06

categorical holds that reason both

play06:07

determines

play06:10

the goals and how to get there so

play06:12

including all the ends and goals of

play06:14

morality so let me say a little more

play06:16

about hypothetical imperatives

play06:19

they state what you should do given a

play06:21

goal that you already have they're not

play06:24

setting the goals they're not telling

play06:26

you what you should what goals you

play06:28

should have

play06:30

it's telling you what goals you should

play06:32

have if you are what you should do if

play06:35

you have another goal so if you want to

play06:37

make a good grade in this class you

play06:40

should work hard on your essays right

play06:43

you should work hard on the reflections

play06:46

if you want to become an attorney you

play06:48

should go to law school because you need

play06:51

to go to law school to become an

play06:52

attorney

play06:54

the should part of these conditionals

play06:56

only apply if you have that particular

play06:59

goal

play07:01

i can't tell you you should go to law

play07:03

school unless you want if you want to be

play07:04

a teacher right

play07:06

you don't need to go to law school you

play07:07

can but that's not usually a way of

play07:10

going about being a teacher

play07:12

if you want to be an engineer i'm not

play07:14

going to tell you you should go to law

play07:15

school if you want to be a doctor i'm

play07:17

not going to tell you should go to law

play07:18

school that only applies the should part

play07:21

you should do this and that's what

play07:23

morality is about right this is what you

play07:25

should do the should part only applies

play07:27

if the if part

play07:28

is true of you

play07:30

if you don't care about making a good

play07:32

grade in the class and then you take it

play07:33

pass or fail and you just want a passing

play07:35

grade then you don't need to work that

play07:37

hard on all the assignments in the class

play07:40

right

play07:41

so the should part only applies if the

play07:43

if part does right

play07:45

categorical imperatives on the other

play07:47

hand that's imperative that's

play07:48

hypothetical categorical imperatives

play07:50

tell you what you should do

play07:53

full stop not if blah blah blah blah

play07:56

this is what you should do they don't

play07:58

depend on whatever goals you have they

play08:01

only depend on reason and they apply to

play08:04

everyone who is rational these are

play08:07

things like thou shalt not kill all of

play08:09

the

play08:10

ten commandments in the hebrew bible

play08:12

christian old testament um are uh are

play08:17

categorical imperatives they're not

play08:18

saying if you want you know

play08:21

to whatever

play08:23

you should

play08:24

cheat on

play08:25

your wife or covet your neighbor's wife

play08:28

it's just saying that um

play08:31

this is what you should do full stop no

play08:33

matter what you are

play08:34

you don't get the option you don't set

play08:36

your goals now kant

play08:38

gives us five different formulas for

play08:41

arriving at the rules that the moral

play08:45

rules that we should follow um we're

play08:47

only going to look at two of those

play08:49

different formulations in his writings

play08:51

although like i said he does five

play08:52

there's three others that we're not

play08:53

going to look at he thinks all of them

play08:56

will give us the same list of rules we

play08:58

don't need the five different ways of

play09:00

talking about the categorical imperative

play09:02

he says there's one categorical

play09:03

imperative and that will generate the

play09:06

rest of the moral rules and he gives us

play09:08

five different formulations of that

play09:09

we're going to talk about two we're

play09:10

going to talk about the universal law of

play09:12

nature formula and we'll talk about the

play09:14

humanity as an n formula i'm going to

play09:16

say them right now

play09:17

and then tell you what each of them are

play09:19

about

play09:20

first the universal law of nature says

play09:22

quote act only in accordance with that

play09:25

maxim through which you can at the same

play09:28

time will that it become a universal law

play09:31

i'm going to explain each part of that

play09:33

later but it says act only in accordance

play09:35

with that maximum through which you can

play09:36

uh at the same time will that have

play09:38

become a universal law that's the

play09:40

universal law of nature formula now the

play09:43

humanity as an n formula says acts so

play09:45

that you treat humanity whether in your

play09:48

own person or in that of another always

play09:50

as an end and never as a means only and

play09:54

you'll see different ways that people

play09:56

translate the german of that

play09:58

but that's those are the ideas of it

play10:00

okay so now let me explain what each of

play10:02

those mean and how they generate the

play10:04

moral laws first let's start with the

play10:06

universal law of nature formula

play10:09

let me say it one more time act only in

play10:11

accordance with that maxim through which

play10:15

you can at the same time will that it

play10:17

become a universal law you might be

play10:20

saying what is a maximum what is a

play10:22

maximum i know that maximum magazine

play10:24

that's not it so i go only in a quarters

play10:26

with a maximum maximum is just a

play10:28

principle or rule something i do not lie

play10:30

do not steal that kind of thing

play10:32

so

play10:34

he's saying that as we come up with

play10:37

actions we come up with a maxim a

play10:40

general rule or principle and

play10:44

we have to

play10:45

put it to a test to see if we can will

play10:49

that that maxim that general rule or uh

play10:53

principle that we're about to act on

play10:55

can it can we wish it consistently

play10:58

logically to be a universal law so it's

play11:01

a logical test it's not can we just want

play11:04

it to be but is it logically possible

play11:08

for us to have that maxim that we're

play11:10

about to act on be

play11:12

universally applied the idea is that

play11:15

categorical imperatives are universal if

play11:18

you can't consistently will that the

play11:21

maxim be applied universal the rule that

play11:23

you're about to act on be applied

play11:25

universally if that results in some kind

play11:27

of logical contradiction then you should

play11:30

not act on that maxim let me tell you it

play11:34

kind of suggests a procedure the the

play11:36

categorical imperative uh the universal

play11:39

uh

play11:40

n formula um

play11:43

the first thing that you do is you think

play11:45

about the action you're about to perform

play11:46

and make it into a universal maximum i'm

play11:48

about to cheat on um my final paper

play11:52

right for dr mcmichael um

play11:56

it is okay to

play11:58

cheat on a final paper if

play12:01

you waited to the last minute to do it

play12:03

that's the maximum right that's the

play12:05

principle that you're about to act on

play12:07

now you want to say what if that were

play12:10

universal for everybody that everybody

play12:13

knew it that everybody acted on that

play12:15

maxim well if it were universal

play12:17

then the the cheating really wouldn't

play12:20

work would it uh you only can get away

play12:23

with cheating is most people do it

play12:25

correctly right cheating doesn't help

play12:26

you if

play12:28

other people are so i'm not going to

play12:29

assign something that can be cheated on

play12:33

if i know that people it's a universally

play12:36

accepted principle that you can cheat on

play12:37

things

play12:39

let's take lying as another instance um

play12:41

if

play12:42

i'm going

play12:43

you're going to lie to me

play12:46

lies only work if i believe you but if i

play12:48

know it's a universal maxim that you can

play12:50

lie to get yourself out of trouble and

play12:51

i'm not going to believe you so it's

play12:53

logically inconsistent so that's the

play12:55

second part of the procedure you think

play12:57

about the action you're about to perform

play12:59

you see if it would be logically

play13:00

possible for you to will that everyone

play13:02

acts on it universally if it's logically

play13:05

possible for you to will that everyone

play13:07

acts on it then it's permissible you're

play13:10

allowed to do it to act on that maximum

play13:12

if it's not logically possible that

play13:14

everyone acts on it then it's not

play13:16

possible to act on it okay

play13:19

again let me give you an example of

play13:20

lying imagine that it's your to your

play13:22

events to lie to me about your homework

play13:25

uh you universalize the act that you're

play13:28

considering to um

play13:30

to act on your universalized into the

play13:33

maxim it is permissible to lie when it

play13:36

is to your advantage okay

play13:38

now that's the maximum you're going to

play13:40

act on your counter it's to my advantage

play13:42

to lie to my professor about my

play13:43

assignment and so

play13:46

it's okay to lie when uh it's to your

play13:48

advantage to do so

play13:50

now you want to test it that's the first

play13:53

of all you take the action you're going

play13:54

to do turn it into a maxim and now you

play13:56

want to test it by the logical test you

play13:58

say can it be universal if everyone act

play14:02

acted on that maxim then no one would

play14:04

have a good reason to believe almost

play14:06

anything anyone else said if it's ever

play14:08

to their advantage to lie i wouldn't

play14:10

believe you right

play14:11

i you need me to believe you in order

play14:14

for a lie to work so it would be

play14:15

ineffective so you can't logically wish

play14:19

that

play14:20

everybody acted on that maximum because

play14:22

then the lie wouldn't work for you

play14:24

therefore it's a contradiction you can't

play14:27

practice it universally without a

play14:28

contradiction so you're making yourself

play14:30

an exception to the rule and this

play14:32

version of the categorical imperative

play14:34

the universal law of nature says that

play14:36

you cannot

play14:38

act on anything that makes yourself an

play14:40

exception so that would not be permitted

play14:43

okay in the next video i'll talk about

play14:44

the humanity as an end formula

Rate This
β˜…
β˜…
β˜…
β˜…
β˜…

5.0 / 5 (0 votes)

Related Tags
Ethical TheoryDeontological EthicsKantian EthicsMoral RulesPhilosophyEthicsReasonConsequentialismVirtue EthicsCategorical Imperative