Augustine & Aquinas: Medieval Political Philosophy

Alexander Koryagin
5 Aug 202215:38

Summary

TLDRThis lecture discusses two prominent figures of Christian philosophy: Augustine and Aquinas. It explores Augustine's pessimistic view of politics and humanity, emphasizing original sin, human evil, and the necessity of strong coercive authority. In contrast, Aquinas, influenced by Aristotle, views politics as integral to human flourishing, advocating for a harmony between material prosperity, moral virtue, and spiritual salvation. The lecture touches on their differing attitudes towards tyranny and authority, setting the stage for later political philosophy discussions, such as those by Hobbes and Locke.

Takeaways

  • 🕰 Augustine and Aquinas stand at two extremes of the Middle Ages, representing different periods and philosophical ideas.
  • 📜 Augustine was an important early Christian philosopher, influenced by Neoplatonism, especially through Plato and Cicero.
  • 😈 Augustine emphasized the concept of original sin, viewing humanity as inherently sinful and deserving of hell.
  • 🛡 Augustine argued that governments are based on coercion, resembling bands of robbers, and saw politics as a necessary evil.
  • 🙏 Augustine believed that Christians should accept their fate under tyranny and martyrdom rather than resist through violence.
  • 🧠 Aquinas, influenced by Aristotle, emphasized the importance of politics and saw it as integral to human flourishing.
  • ⚖ Aquinas introduced the idea of natural law, suggesting that moral truths are accessible to all rational beings through reason.
  • đŸ’„ Unlike Augustine, Aquinas allowed for the possibility of resistance against tyrants, though in a limited and structured way.
  • 👑 Aquinas supported monarchy as the best form of government but with checks and balances, resembling a mixed regime.
  • 🔗 The ideas of both Augustine and Aquinas influenced later political thought, notably Hobbes' realism and Locke's natural law.

Q & A

  • Who are the two key philosophers discussed in the script?

    -The two key philosophers discussed are Augustine of Hippo and Thomas Aquinas, who represent two extremes of the Christian Middle Ages.

  • How did Augustine initially view Christianity?

    -Augustine initially found Christianity to be intellectually unsophisticated and was influenced by the works of Cicero and Neoplatonism before fully accepting Christian doctrine.

  • What is Augustine's view on original sin and human nature?

    -Augustine believed that humanity is inherently sinful due to the original sin of Adam, and that everyone deserves to go to hell unless saved by God's inscrutable mercy.

  • How does Augustine view politics and government?

    -Augustine sees politics as a necessary evil. He believes that governments are fundamentally coercive and that there is little difference between a government and a band of robbers.

  • What is Augustine's stance on resistance to tyrants?

    -Augustine believed that Christians must submit to authority and only offer non-violent, passive resistance if commanded to act against their faith, such as being forced to sacrifice to pagan deities.

  • How does Aquinas' view of politics differ from Augustine's?

    -Aquinas viewed political engagement as integral to human flourishing, unlike Augustine, who was anti-political. Aquinas believed in the possibility of harmony between material prosperity, virtuous character, and spiritual salvation.

  • What role does natural law play in Aquinas' philosophy?

    -Aquinas believed that natural law, knowable through reason, governs universal moral truths. This law applies to all rational human beings, regardless of whether they are Christian.

  • Does Aquinas believe in the right to resist tyranny?

    -Yes, Aquinas suggests that if positive laws conflict with natural law, they are not legitimate, and there may be a right of revolution, though likely through the actions of inferior magistrates rather than individuals.

  • What form of government does Aquinas support?

    -Aquinas favored monarchy, arguing that one ruler mirrors the singular authority of God, though he also advocated for a mixed regime with elements of aristocracy and possibly democratic representation.

  • What connection is drawn between Augustine, Aquinas, and later philosophers?

    -The script highlights Augustine’s influence on thinkers like Thomas Hobbes, especially in the realist tradition, and Aquinas’ influence on philosophers like John Locke, particularly regarding natural law.

Outlines

00:00

⏳ Rushing through the Christian Middle Ages: Augustine and Aquinas

The speaker introduces the need to briefly cover centuries of Christian Middle Ages history, focusing on two influential figures—Augustine and Aquinas. Augustine, a major early Christian philosopher, initially viewed the gospel as intellectually unsophisticated. His ideas were heavily influenced by Neoplatonism, especially Plotinus. Augustine's philosophy reflects a pessimistic view of humanity, marred by original sin, where everyone deserves to go to hell, and God's mercy alone decides salvation. His ideas on politics equate governments with bands of robbers, emphasizing the harsh necessity of coercion to govern a fundamentally evil human nature.

05:02

🛡 Augustine's Stance on Tyranny and Heresy

This paragraph delves into Augustine’s harsh stance on heretics and his justification for coercive power. Augustine justifies the use of imperial power against Christian sects that do not align with the Bishop of Rome. He also discusses tyranny, emphasizing that Christians should obey authority as all power comes from God, except when commanded to do something against their faith. In such cases, Augustine advocates for passive resistance and martyrdom, believing that eternal rewards in the afterlife outweigh any earthly suffering.

10:02

⚖ Augustine vs. Aquinas: A Shift in Political Thought

The speaker contrasts Augustine's and Aquinas's political philosophies. While Augustine sees politics as a necessary evil, Aquinas, influenced by Aristotle, rehabilitates political life as integral to human flourishing. Augustine’s strict dichotomy of loving God versus loving oneself is replaced by Aquinas’s belief in the possibility of harmony between material prosperity, virtue, and salvation. Aquinas also promotes the idea that reason and natural law can guide humanity, regardless of religion, and that revelation complements rather than contradicts natural law.

15:03

🌍 Aquinas and Natural Law: Universal Morality and the Right to Resist Tyranny

Aquinas argues that universal norms of morality, or natural law, can be established by reason alone, accessible to all people, regardless of their faith. He believes natural law forms the foundation of a harmonious society, supplemented by divine commandments. Aquinas’s approach to tyranny is also different from Augustine’s; he suggests that unjust laws conflicting with natural law can be resisted, and there is a limited right to revolution, especially by magistrates or princes, although not fully fleshed out in his work.

👑 Monarchy and Mixed Regime: Aquinas’s Ideal Government

Aquinas, drawing from Aristotle, supports monarchy as the best form of government, though his concept is more aligned with a mixed regime, similar to the rule of Moses in the Bible. The speaker reflects on how Aquinas’s preference for monarchy might seem antiquated but invites students to consider how future generations might view modern political ideas as equally outdated. Aquinas's monarchy includes elements of checks and balances, such as an aristocratic council and some democratic representation, blending various forms of governance.

🔄 Revisiting Realism and Natural Law: Themes for the Future

The speaker briefly concludes by noting the importance of revisiting Augustine's pessimistic realism, especially in thinkers like Thomas Hobbes, and Aquinas’s concept of natural law, which will appear later in thinkers like John Locke. Locke borrows from Aquinas’s idea that natural law is knowable through reason, influencing later political and philosophical discussions.

Mindmap

Keywords

💡Augustine

Augustine, a key early Christian philosopher from the 4th and 5th centuries, plays a crucial role in shaping medieval Christian thought. In the video, he is depicted as having a deeply pessimistic view of humanity, influenced by his belief in original sin. Augustine views politics as a necessary evil and believes that salvation is only attainable through God's grace, often placing more emphasis on spiritual matters over earthly concerns.

💡Original Sin

Original sin refers to the doctrine, rooted in Augustine’s theology, that all humans inherit a sinful nature due to Adam's fall in the Garden of Eden. Augustine argues that this sin makes human beings inherently evil, deserving of eternal punishment, but God, in his mercy, chooses to save a select few. This concept is central to Augustine’s pessimistic view of humanity and his belief that political systems must be harsh to counter human wickedness.

💡Neoplatonism

Neoplatonism, a philosophical system that Augustine encountered through reading Plotinus, played a significant role in his conversion to Christianity. This school of thought emphasizes the existence of a higher, immaterial reality, which Augustine uses as a framework to understand Christian doctrines, such as the nature of the soul and salvation. In the video, it is highlighted how Augustine integrates Neoplatonic ideas with Christian theology.

💡Coercion and Politics

Augustine viewed politics as inherently based on coercion and violence, likening governments to 'bands of robbers.' He believed that no government could truly be just, as human nature is corrupt due to original sin. Therefore, political authority, though necessary, is always tainted and should focus on restraining evil rather than achieving justice.

💡City of God vs. City of Man

Augustine's concept of the 'City of God' versus the 'City of Man' contrasts the heavenly realm, where true justice and divine order prevail, with the earthly, sinful world. According to Augustine, earthly governments belong to the 'City of Man' and are inherently flawed, whereas the 'City of God' represents the ultimate goal of Christian life, attainable only after death. This dichotomy illustrates his anti-political stance and the focus on spiritual salvation.

💡Thomas Aquinas

Thomas Aquinas, a 13th-century philosopher and theologian, contrasts with Augustine by viewing politics and engagement in public life as essential to human flourishing. In the video, Aquinas is presented as more optimistic, following Aristotelian principles and arguing that political life and virtue are integral to achieving happiness and harmony. Aquinas also sees no conflict between reason and faith, promoting the idea that both can lead to truth.

💡Natural Law

Natural law, as emphasized by Aquinas, is the belief that moral principles are inherent in human nature and accessible through reason. Aquinas argues that these universal truths are knowable by all rational beings, regardless of their religious background. In the video, this contrasts with Augustine’s more pessimistic outlook, as Aquinas believes that societies can operate justly based on natural law.

💡Tyranny

The video contrasts Augustine and Aquinas’s views on tyranny. Augustine advocates for passive resistance and martyrdom when faced with tyrannical rulers, suggesting that Christians should accept suffering as part of their faith. Aquinas, however, introduces the idea that unjust laws, which violate natural law, may be resisted. While not fully endorsing revolution, Aquinas acknowledges the possibility of resisting tyranny under certain circumstances, particularly by 'inferior magistrates.'

💡Faith and Reason

Both Augustine and Aquinas discuss the relationship between faith and reason, but they approach it differently. Augustine believes that reason has limits and must be supplemented by divine revelation, particularly when it comes to understanding God’s will. Aquinas, in contrast, holds that reason and faith work in harmony, with reason capable of discovering truths about the world and morality, while revelation completes this knowledge. This is a core theme in Aquinas’s philosophy, bridging religious belief and intellectual inquiry.

💡Martyrdom

In Augustine’s philosophy, martyrdom is the ultimate response to political tyranny. He argues that Christians should submit to unjust authorities, but if forced to act against their faith, they should refuse and accept death as a martyr. This approach emphasizes Augustine's belief in the futility of worldly power and the importance of spiritual integrity over political resistance.

Highlights

Augustine begins his education as an academic skeptic by reading Cicero, finding Christianity initially intellectually unsophisticated.

Augustine embraces Christianity through the influence of Neoplatonism, particularly the work of Plotinus.

A central question about Augustine's philosophy is how much he owes to the Bible versus how much he owes to Plato.

Augustine views politics as a necessary evil, with humanity inherently infected by original sin.

Augustine argues that all human beings, including saints and newborns, deserve damnation because of original sin, and salvation is only possible through God's inscrutable mercy.

In Augustine's view, governments resemble bands of robbers, as both rely on coercion and violence.

Augustine sees life as a 'veil of tears,' and this world as merely a preparation for the afterlife, with no expectation of justice on earth.

Christians in positions of power, according to Augustine, must exercise coercive force to curb human evil.

Augustine controversially defends the use of violent coercion against heretics to preserve orthodoxy.

Despite his pessimism about earthly life, Augustine advises Christians to accept martyrdom when resisting tyranny.

Aquinas, in contrast, sees political participation as integral to human flourishing, aligning more with Aristotelian philosophy.

Aquinas rehabilitates political life, seeing it as compatible with virtue and material prosperity, in contrast to Augustine's anti-political stance.

Aquinas argues that natural law, knowable by reason alone, provides a moral foundation for all human beings, regardless of religion.

For Aquinas, human laws must conform to natural law; if they conflict, they are unjust and may be resisted.

Aquinas advocates monarchy as the best form of government but acknowledges the importance of checks and balances, resembling Aristotle's mixed regime.

Transcripts

play00:00

[Music]

play00:04

alas

play00:05

time is short

play00:06

and so lamentably we're going to have to

play00:08

rush

play00:10

through several centuries of the

play00:12

christian middle ages but

play00:14

as an example we're going to talk about

play00:17

again two figures who stand at the

play00:21

roughly speaking at the two extremes of

play00:23

the middle ages augustine in the fourth

play00:25

and fifth centuries and aquinas in the

play00:27

13th century

play00:29

so um

play00:31

as always i'm brief and brief and

play00:33

superficial presentation but still

play00:36

um

play00:37

augustine

play00:38

is a very important uh um philosopher of

play00:41

uh of early christianity and again to

play00:44

continue this

play00:45

um discussion of of difference between

play00:49

christianity of jesus and christianity

play00:51

in rome right

play00:54

lamentably i have to i have to mention

play00:55

this right

play00:56

augustine uh um begins his education as

play01:00

an as an academic skeptic by reading

play01:02

cicero and i guess augustine's mother is

play01:05

a christian but he finds the christian

play01:07

gospel to be let's say intellectually

play01:09

unsophisticated

play01:11

so augustine cannot really become a

play01:13

christian before he goes through a stage

play01:16

he reads neoplatonists and only through

play01:19

the prism of neoplateness first and

play01:21

foremost presumably platinus he then

play01:24

comes to accept the

play01:26

uh the christian doctrine but a big

play01:29

question you know how much does

play01:30

augustine owe to the bible and how much

play01:32

does he owe to plato

play01:35

anyway

play01:36

still sort of within this uh uh broad

play01:39

and superficial comparison augustine

play01:41

should remind us of plato or at least of

play01:43

a certain neoplatonic version of plato

play01:45

with this insistence that

play01:49

politics is a necessary evil

play01:51

and in general augustine's outlook is

play01:53

deeply deeply pessimistic in this notion

play01:55

that humanity is infected with original

play01:59

sin the original sin of adam and so

play02:03

human beings are by nature evil

play02:06

and in fact augustine is very adamant

play02:09

that everybody deserves to go to hell

play02:11

because of this original sin um even the

play02:14

same tastes of saints even the newborn

play02:16

babies deserve to go to hell and god

play02:20

only by his infinite mercy completely

play02:22

undeservedly decides to save uh certain

play02:26

people now god's reasons are inscrutable

play02:28

to us so god is just in the end but

play02:32

we cannot even predict who's going to be

play02:34

saved because technically speaking

play02:35

everybody deserves to go to hell right

play02:37

and so again so original sin the the

play02:40

evil of human nature and so augustine in

play02:43

a move which is actually reminiscent of

play02:45

the sophists

play02:46

talks maybe of thrasymachus he talks

play02:48

about how there is no justice on this

play02:50

earth

play02:51

and governments at best can resemble a

play02:54

band of robbers there's no there is you

play02:55

know

play02:56

politics is based on coercion violence

play02:59

and there is no interesting difference

play03:01

in principle between governments and the

play03:03

band of robbers both are based on on

play03:06

coercion

play03:07

um at the same time um

play03:10

augustine

play03:11

so i mean like in in general his general

play03:14

attitude to to life is that this life

play03:16

again is a veil of tears or a welter of

play03:19

sorrow so

play03:21

again in this anti-political fashion um

play03:25

christians have nothing to gain in this

play03:28

life this is this life is only a short

play03:30

preparation for judgment and eternal

play03:32

life after death which is now understood

play03:34

in terms of not in terms of the physical

play03:36

resurrection of the body but in terms of

play03:38

the neoplatonic immortal soul

play03:41

right but um

play03:44

still to the extent to the extent that

play03:48

some people some christians can find

play03:50

themselves in a position of power and

play03:52

authority

play03:53

um christians have to exercise this

play03:56

power and authority in harsh and

play03:58

coercive ways

play03:59

again human beings are bad and so uh

play04:02

governments through harsh coercive

play04:04

action have to try to make them less bad

play04:08

and this is actually again

play04:10

augustine is a deeply deeply

play04:12

controversial

play04:13

uh thinker

play04:15

throughout the rest of the history of

play04:17

western philosophy and especially this

play04:18

idea of original sin many later

play04:20

philosophers will find this to be a

play04:22

terrible doctrine and you know

play04:25

linked to this also is going to be

play04:27

augustine's attitude towards heretics

play04:29

because within the catholic tradition

play04:31

augustine

play04:34

serves as the most important defender of

play04:36

the practice of violent coercion of

play04:39

heretics

play04:41

this this notion that human beings are

play04:42

sinful so

play04:44

um even though technically speaking

play04:47

people

play04:48

believe with their heart and um in this

play04:51

in this sense like it should be like

play04:54

it's theoretically i guess impossible to

play04:56

force people into the right kind of

play04:58

belief however there is a role of for

play05:01

violence and coercion in putting down

play05:04

heresies and again this uh again

play05:07

augustine serves as the justification of

play05:09

the

play05:10

centralized imperial power being

play05:12

deployed against um christian

play05:15

monasteries again versions of

play05:16

christianity which do not subscribe to

play05:19

the bishop of rome

play05:21

to the ideas of the bishop of rome who

play05:23

gradually over time acquires the status

play05:25

as the pope status which is not really

play05:28

found in early christian communities or

play05:30

for that matter

play05:31

in the christian scripture

play05:34

so maybe to try to illustrate

play05:35

augustine's position maybe with a

play05:36

slightly more vivid example so if you

play05:38

talk about tyranny or tyrants again in

play05:40

general augustine places places very low

play05:42

value on this life

play05:45

and so

play05:46

uh in principle again all power comes

play05:48

from god we are not supposed to resist

play05:50

evil so

play05:53

and again all power is from god so

play05:55

christians always have to obey however

play05:57

if the tyrant forces you to do something

play06:00

completely antithetical to your faith

play06:02

like for example um sacrifice to the

play06:05

pagan deities which incidentally was the

play06:09

uh um original problem that the roman

play06:11

empire had with the christians roman

play06:12

empire in general was very tolerant of

play06:15

many different faiths against idea of

play06:17

syncretism let's just add on

play06:19

different gods to the pantheon however

play06:22

the christian refusal to sacrifice to

play06:24

the statue of the emperor the christian

play06:26

refusal to sacrifice to the statue of

play06:28

the emperor this was seen

play06:30

as political treason and this is

play06:32

basically why christians were persecuted

play06:33

not necessarily for their religious

play06:35

ideas so again so augustine would say

play06:37

that christians always have to submit

play06:39

but if they are forced to do something

play06:41

which is completely against their faith

play06:44

then

play06:44

um they can only offer a non-violent

play06:48

passive resistance and accept their just

play06:51

punishment so basically martyr them so

play06:53

the answer to the problem of tyranny in

play06:55

augustine is martyrdom you accept the

play06:58

death of the martyr and you hope that

play07:00

god will reward you in the afterlife

play07:03

again this is augustine and although

play07:05

it's very important that augustine is

play07:06

not plato and i think that the very

play07:09

there are very clear uh differences

play07:11

between pagustine worldview and platonic

play07:13

worldview even if we talk about the um

play07:16

republic right so um

play07:19

plato or socrates and plato's republic

play07:22

talks about this intellectual

play07:24

contemplation of the forms and maybe

play07:27

the form of the good which seems to be

play07:29

impersonal

play07:31

right but in in augustine uh we're not

play07:34

we're no longer talking about this form

play07:36

of the good now we're talking about a

play07:38

personal god and so in in general

play07:41

there's a basic compatibility between

play07:44

philosophy and religion in august and

play07:46

augustine has this very famous phrase

play07:49

we do philosophy because faith is

play07:50

seeking understanding but again

play07:53

again in the skeptical move

play07:55

reason establishes its own boundaries

play07:58

reason establishes its own limitation

play08:00

and we have to refer to revelation to

play08:02

supplement reason

play08:04

so this this is augustine

play08:06

and again i hope you can see platonic

play08:08

elements in augustine's doctrine

play08:10

so rushing through the centuries now we

play08:12

get to aquinas

play08:14

um

play08:15

aristotle's works are actually

play08:17

rediscovered reintroduced into europe uh

play08:20

by way of the islamic world and by way

play08:23

of

play08:24

islamic arabic and jewish commentators

play08:26

on aristotle it's a whole separate story

play08:28

unfortunately we have to

play08:29

gloss over uh uh but again you can see

play08:32

aquinas's uh um

play08:35

attitude to politics and to life in

play08:36

general is very different right so

play08:38

whereas again augustine in this somewhat

play08:41

platonic fashion talks about politics as

play08:43

necessary evil aquinas in aristotelian

play08:45

fashion is going to say that engaging in

play08:47

politics

play08:48

is integral to human flourishing so

play08:52

augustine is deeply anti-political and

play08:54

in aquinas we see a certain

play08:56

rehabilitation of political life this is

play08:58

later going to be important for the

play09:00

republican tradition

play09:02

uh uh republican in a sense of the word

play09:05

republicanism has different meanings in

play09:07

this context we mean the value of

play09:09

political political participation in and

play09:11

of itself

play09:12

um so so whereas for augustine augustine

play09:16

has this very radical formulation he

play09:17

talks about these two cities the earthly

play09:19

city and the heavenly city and augustine

play09:21

basically says you either have to love

play09:23

god and hate yourself this notion of

play09:26

original sin or you have to if you love

play09:29

yourself then you have to hate god

play09:31

augustine is very uncompromising in this

play09:33

in the sense

play09:35

aquinas does not see this as a conflict

play09:37

he's going to say

play09:39

look

play09:40

the task of the good life is to be

play09:42

prosperous including presumably having

play09:44

some measure of property or maybe luxury

play09:46

so this material prosperity and also

play09:48

virtual and excellence of character

play09:50

and salvation of your soul and there's

play09:53

there's a possibility of harmony between

play09:55

all three of these at the same time

play09:58

right and in general when aquinas talks

play10:02

about reason and revelation aquinas

play10:04

writes extensively to the gentiles

play10:05

mostly meaning

play10:08

jews and muslims but aquinas imagines

play10:10

again in this quasi-aristotelian fashion

play10:13

which should be reminiscent also of the

play10:14

stoics that reason establishes universal

play10:18

norms of morality that there is a

play10:20

natural law and this natural law is

play10:22

clear and knowable to all rational human

play10:25

beings regardless of whether they are

play10:27

christians or not and yes in addition to

play10:29

this natural law

play10:31

the yahweh also reveals particular

play10:33

commandments

play10:35

but

play10:36

first they do not

play10:37

contradict mature law in any fashion and

play10:40

in fact they sort of complete and

play10:41

supplement the natural law but there is

play10:44

a basis for

play10:46

good and harmonious existence for all

play10:49

peoples in some sense regardless of

play10:51

whether they're christians or not and

play10:52

again in aquinas there's this deep

play10:54

commitment

play10:55

to the fact that the basic truths

play10:58

of life can be established through

play11:01

reason alone to reason alone now

play11:03

reason alone or philosophy alone will

play11:05

not get you all the way and in order to

play11:07

be perfectly virtuous in order to be

play11:09

perfectly happy and in order to go to

play11:11

paradise or to heaven after you die you

play11:13

also need the benefit of revelation but

play11:16

again uh these two these two work much

play11:19

more um

play11:21

together in in in concert and again we

play11:24

asked this question about tyranny and

play11:26

tyrants in augustine the only suggestion

play11:28

the only advice that augustine gives is

play11:30

except the death of the martyr and

play11:32

aquinas is different in aquinas is

play11:33

different aquinas is going to say that

play11:35

the positive laws of society

play11:37

if they conflict with the natural laws

play11:39

then there are no no laws at all now

play11:42

aquinas doesn't have a fully fledged

play11:44

political philosophy but in general

play11:46

there is something like an intimation to

play11:49

the right of revolution now

play11:52

we have to be careful um

play11:54

this is probably not the right of

play11:57

individuals to resist uh the governments

play12:00

right because at the sa at the uh you

play12:01

know at the end of the day all power

play12:02

comes from god but there's a certain

play12:04

notion that maybe inferior magistrates

play12:07

inferior magistrates maybe not private

play12:10

individuals but let's say princes

play12:12

can uh legitimately

play12:15

uh

play12:16

resist you know even violently resist uh

play12:19

um you know a king who has become a

play12:21

tyrant

play12:22

right so so so again whereas augustine

play12:24

simply enjoins us to accept our fate uh

play12:28

um aquinas actually has

play12:31

uh a limited defense of again

play12:34

um

play12:35

right you revolution violent resistance

play12:37

overthrow of tyrants although again

play12:39

although it's not it's not really

play12:40

perfectly fleshed out now one last thing

play12:43

i want to mention that you will remember

play12:45

when we talked about aristotle there was

play12:46

a typology of regimes

play12:48

and um again i think it's a very

play12:50

interesting intellectual exercise

play12:52

for us to look at

play12:54

what was considered the best regime

play12:56

throughout the ages now for aquinas in

play12:58

the middle ages it's very clear that of

play13:00

course the best regime and again i

play13:02

remind you aquinas is reading aristotle

play13:03

and he's trying to base his philosophy

play13:04

aristotle aquinas is going to say that

play13:06

the best regime is monarchy

play13:08

right and this

play13:10

sounds preposterous to many students and

play13:12

aquinas gives some arguments he says

play13:14

there's only one god therefore

play13:17

there should be one king

play13:20

right but i think there's a there's a

play13:22

deeply you know there's a very important

play13:23

intellectual exercise in us looking at

play13:25

what aquinas is saying no

play13:27

this should teach us a little bit of

play13:29

humility right i i i believe i don't

play13:31

want to say i believe but i invite you

play13:33

colleagues to think about uh the

play13:35

medieval prejudice about monarchy being

play13:37

the best form of government and also to

play13:39

think of what we today think are the

play13:41

best forms of government could it be

play13:43

that future generations will regard our

play13:45

political ideas as preposterous right as

play13:48

the ideas people had in the middle ages

play13:51

now to be perfectly to be perfectly fair

play13:53

to aquinas his um

play13:55

idea of the virtuous monarchy is

play13:57

actually closer to aristotle's mixed

play13:59

regime aquinas's own example would be

play14:01

moses

play14:02

who rules moses in the hebrew bible who

play14:05

rules as a single king

play14:07

but

play14:08

relying on the council of the elders so

play14:12

there is some

play14:14

some intimation of you know separation

play14:16

of powers or at least

play14:17

something like checks and balances

play14:19

between the monarch the uh uh you know

play14:22

the aristocratic you know the single

play14:24

monarch the aristocratic assembly of the

play14:26

elders and then maybe even um in some

play14:29

form the democratic representation of

play14:31

the people so

play14:32

not necessarily monarchy in its pure

play14:35

form but something closer to a mixed

play14:37

regime

play14:39

unfortunately on this note we're going

play14:40

to have to finish our extremely brief

play14:42

discussion of these

play14:44

uh two profound thinkers however uh let

play14:48

me just allude to the fact that we're

play14:50

going to return to these ideas again

play14:52

this uh

play14:54

realist tradition in politics how

play14:57

human beings are by nature evil in

play14:59

augustine and therefore

play15:00

society has to be based on a strong

play15:03

coercive authority

play15:05

especially in the philosophy of thomas

play15:06

hobbs we'll see something similar and

play15:08

likewise a different perspective in

play15:10

aquinas especially this notion of

play15:11

natural law which is knowable through

play15:14

reason and available to all rational

play15:15

human beings again this is an idea we'll

play15:18

return back to especially in the in the

play15:21

works of

play15:22

uh john locke who i think quite

play15:24

explicitly

play15:26

borrows many of his ideas from the

play15:29

legacy of thomas aquinas

play15:33

[Music]

Rate This
★
★
★
★
★

5.0 / 5 (0 votes)

Étiquettes Connexes
ChristianityMiddle AgesAugustineAquinasPhilosophyOriginal SinPoliticsNatural LawFaith vs ReasonTheology
Besoin d'un résumé en anglais ?