An Explanation of Terminology used in Metaethics

Jeffrey Kaplan
9 Mar 202022:27

Summary

TLDRThe script discusses moral philosophy, contrasting moral objectivism, which asserts universal moral facts, with moral skepticism and relativism, which deny such facts. It explores consequentialism, where moral value is based on outcomes, and non-consequentialism, which looks to action intentions or characteristics. The script also introduces moral subjectivism, ethical relativism, and moral nihilism, concluding with a critique of moral skepticism and an argument for the existence of moral facts independent of our terminology.

Takeaways

  • ๐Ÿ“š The script is a discussion about moral philosophy, focusing on whether there are objective moral facts that apply universally.
  • ๐ŸŒ Moral objectivism is the belief that there are universal moral facts that everyone should adhere to, regardless of personal beliefs.
  • ๐Ÿ” The script explores different moral theories, including consequentialism, which asserts that the morality of actions is determined by their consequences.
  • ๐Ÿค” Moral skepticism questions the existence of objective moral facts, suggesting that what's right or wrong may vary based on individual or societal context.
  • ๐Ÿ‘ค Moral subjectivism is the view that moral facts differ for each individual, meaning actions are right or wrong based on one's own moral code.
  • ๐ŸŒ Moral relativism posits that moral facts are relative to a culture or society, with different moral systems being correct within their own context.
  • ๐Ÿšซ Moral nihilism is the extreme stance that there are no moral facts at all, rendering all moral claims meaningless.
  • ๐Ÿ—ฃ๏ธ Error theory is the idea that all moral statements are false because there are no moral facts to support them.
  • ๐Ÿ“– The script mentions Schaeffer Landau's argument against moral skepticism, suggesting that just because we create moral vocabulary doesn't mean we create the moral facts themselves.
  • ๐ŸŒŒ The script uses the analogy of the Flat Earth theory to illustrate error theory, comparing it to moral claims that are believed to be entirely false.

Q & A

  • What is the central question of the second chapter of Schaeffer Landau's book?

    -The central question is whether there are objective, universal moral facts that apply to everyone, everywhere, about what's right and what's wrong.

  • What is the term for the view that there are moral facts that apply to everyone everywhere?

    -The term for this view is 'moral objectivism'.

  • What is consequentialism, and who is an example of a consequentialist?

    -Consequentialism is the view that the moral rightness or wrongness of actions is determined by their consequences. An example of a consequentialist is Jeremy Bentham.

  • What does it mean to be a moral skeptic?

    -A moral skeptic is someone who believes that there are no objective or universal moral facts.

  • What is moral subjectivism, and how does it differ from moral objectivism?

    -Moral subjectivism is the view that there are no objective, universal moral facts, but there are moral facts that are different for each person. It differs from moral objectivism by asserting that moral facts are relative to the individual, rather than universal.

  • What is moral relativism, and how does it differ from moral subjectivism?

    -Moral relativism is the view that moral facts are relative to a culture or society, and what is morally right or wrong varies between societies. It differs from moral subjectivism in that moral facts are relative to a society rather than an individual.

  • What is moral nihilism, and how does it relate to the existence of moral facts?

    -Moral nihilism is the view that there are no moral facts at all, neither objective nor relative. It denies the existence of any kind of moral facts or laws.

  • What is an error theory in the context of moral discourse?

    -An error theory in moral discourse is the claim that all moral statements are false because there are no moral facts to which these statements could correspond.

  • What is the difference between an error theory and a non-cognitive theory of moral statements?

    -An error theory claims that moral statements are false because there are no moral facts. A non-cognitive theory, on the other hand, suggests that moral statements do not have truth-value and are instead expressions of sentiment or attitudes.

  • What is the argument Schaeffer Landau presents against moral skepticism?

    -The argument against moral skepticism is that just because we invented the terms 'right' and 'wrong' does not mean we invented the concepts of rightness or wrongness. It's a distinction between the vocabulary we create and the facts or entities that exist independently of our language.

  • What is the significance of the vocabulary versus facts distinction in moral philosophy?

    -The significance lies in understanding that the creation of moral vocabulary does not necessarily imply the creation of the moral facts themselves. This distinction helps to clarify that moral facts could exist independently of our language about them.

Outlines

00:00

๐Ÿ“š Introduction to Moral Objectivism and Skepticism

The script begins with a critique of moral skepticism, suggesting that the entire theory is a mistake. It then introduces the concept of moral objectivism, which asserts that there are universal moral facts that apply to everyone, regardless of personal beliefs. The author, Schaeffer Landau, defends moral objectivism in his book. The video also touches on consequentialism, the idea that the morality of actions is determined by their consequences, and non-consequentialism, which posits that actions have moral value beyond their outcomes. The script sets the stage for a discussion on moral relativism and subjectivism, which will be explored in subsequent paragraphs.

05:01

๐ŸŒ Moral Relativism and Subjectivism

This paragraph delves into moral relativism and subjectivism. Moral relativism suggests that moral facts are not universal but vary based on societal or cultural context. For example, an action considered moral in one society might be immoral in another. Moral subjectivism, on the other hand, posits that moral facts are personal and that each individual has their own moral code. An action is only immoral if it violates an individual's own moral standards. The script also introduces moral nihilism, the belief that there are no moral facts at all, and error theory, which claims that all moral statements are false because there are no moral facts to support them.

10:02

๐Ÿ—ฃ๏ธ Error Theory and Non-Cognitivism

The script discusses error theory in the context of moral discourse, suggesting that if one believes there are no moral facts, then all moral statements are false. It provides an analogy with Flat Earth theory, which is also considered an error theory because the Earth is not flat. The paragraph also introduces non-cognitivism, the view that moral statements do not express truth claims but are instead expressions of sentiment or attitude. Non-cognitivists argue that moral language does not have cognitive significance and cannot be true or false.

15:04

๐ŸŒŸ The Distinction Between Vocabulary and Facts

This section argues against the assumption that because we create moral vocabulary, we also create the moral facts themselves. Schaeffer Landau uses the analogy of the word 'planet' to illustrate that while we invented the word, the celestial bodies it describes existed long before human language. He suggests that the same could be true for moral terms like 'right' and 'wrong'; just because we use these terms does not mean we created the moral facts they refer to. The paragraph serves as a defense of moral objectivism, implying that moral facts may exist independently of our language and terminology.

20:07

๐Ÿ” The Argument Against Moral Skepticism

The final paragraph summarizes the argument against moral skepticism presented in the script. It emphasizes the distinction between inventing moral vocabulary and inventing moral facts. Schaeffer Landau argues that just because humans created the terms used to describe moral concepts does not mean that humans also created the moral facts these terms refer to. The paragraph reinforces the idea that moral facts might exist independently of our language, challenging the skeptic's view that there are no objective moral truths.

Mindmap

Keywords

๐Ÿ’กMoral Objectivism

Moral Objectivism is the philosophical stance that there are objective moral facts that apply universally, regardless of individual or cultural differences. In the script, the author defends this view, suggesting that certain actions are inherently right or wrong. This is central to the video's theme as it sets the stage for discussing moral facts and their universality.

๐Ÿ’กConsequentialism

Consequentialism is the ethical theory that the moral value of an action is determined by its consequences. The script mentions Andrew Bentham as a consequentialist, emphasizing that if the outcomes of actions dictate their moral worth, then one aligns with this view. This concept is pivotal as it contrasts with other theories that might base morality on intentions or virtues.

๐Ÿ’กNon-Consequentialism

Non-Consequentialism is the belief that the morality of an action is not solely based on its consequences. The script contrasts this with consequentialism, citing Aristotle and Kant as proponents. For Aristotle, moral worth comes from the nature of the action itself in relation to human virtue, while Kant believed it derived from the maxims underlying the action. This keyword is crucial for understanding the diversity of moral theories.

๐Ÿ’กMoral Skepticism

Moral Skepticism is the view that there are no objective or universal moral facts. The script suggests that if one denies the existence of universal moral truths, they are a moral skeptic. This term is integral to the video's narrative as it presents an alternative to moral objectivism and consequentialism, introducing the idea of moral relativity or subjectivity.

๐Ÿ’กMoral Relativism

Moral Relativism is the position that moral principles are not absolute but may vary among different societies or cultures. The script explains this by suggesting that what is morally permissible can differ based on societal norms. This keyword is significant as it challenges the universal applicability of moral principles discussed earlier in the video.

๐Ÿ’กMoral Subjectivism

Moral Subjectivism is the idea that moral truths are determined by individual perspectives rather than objective standards. The script illustrates this by proposing that each person has their own moral code, which is right for them. This concept is key to understanding personal morality and how it contrasts with universal moral facts.

๐Ÿ’กMoral Nihilism

Moral Nihilism is the belief that there are no moral facts or objective moral values at all. The script describes this as the view that nothing is inherently morally good or bad. This keyword is central to the video's exploration of moral skepticism and the potential extremes of denying moral truths.

๐Ÿ’กError Theory

Error Theory, as discussed in the script, is the idea that all moral claims are false because there are no moral facts to which they could correspond. It is presented as a response to moral nihilism, where if one believes there are no moral facts, then all moral statements are mistaken. This keyword is important for understanding the implications of denying moral objectivity.

๐Ÿ’กNon-Cognitivism

Non-Cognitivism is the view that moral statements do not express factual claims and thus cannot be true or false. The script mentions this in the context of explaining moral discourse if one believes moral claims are not truth-apt. This concept is significant for understanding an alternative approach to moral language that does not rely on truth values.

๐Ÿ’กTerminology

Terminology, as used in the script, refers to the specific words or phrases used to convey concepts. The discussion around 'terminology' versus 'facts' is crucial as it distinguishes between the human-made language used to describe moral concepts and the independent existence of those moral facts. This keyword is foundational to the video's argument about the potential objectivity of moral facts.

๐Ÿ’กMoral Discourse

Moral Discourse refers to conversations or discussions about moral issues, principles, or judgments. The script explores the implications of moral nihilism and error theory on moral discourse, questioning the validity of such discussions if there are no moral facts. This keyword is essential for understanding the practical impact of various moral philosophies on how we talk about ethics.

Highlights

The transcript discusses the central question of moral philosophy: Are there objective, universal moral facts?

Moral objectivism is the view that there are moral facts that apply to everyone, everywhere.

Consequentialism is the view that the morality of actions is determined by their consequences.

Non-consequentialism, as seen in Aristotle's philosophy, holds that actions have moral value beyond their consequences.

Kant's non-consequentialism suggests moral rightness is based on the maxim of actions, not just intentions.

Moral skepticism doubts the existence of objective or universal moral facts.

Relativism proposes that moral facts vary based on societal or contextual differences.

Moral subjectivism is the stance that each person has their own moral code that is right for them.

Ethical or moral relativism asserts that moral facts are relative to a culture or society.

Moral nihilism denies the existence of any moral facts, objective or non-objective.

Error theory claims that all moral statements are false because there are no moral facts.

Non-cognitivism suggests that moral statements do not have truth-value and are expressions of sentiment.

The chapter introduces a defense of moral objectivism against moral skepticism.

The argument against moral skepticism draws a distinction between vocabulary and facts or entities.

Shafer Landau argues that inventing moral terms does not imply we invented the moral facts themselves.

The chapter lays out the moral landscape, setting the stage for deeper philosophical discussions.

Transcripts

play00:00

they're all false it's a whole big

play00:02

mistake all this whole this whole theory

play00:04

is just one mistake it's one big error

play00:06

and every single statement that they

play00:08

make is a falsehood false false false

play00:13

that's an error theory

play00:15

[Music]

play00:23

all right this is gonna be a boring one

play00:26

this was a boring chapter and this is

play00:29

gonna be a boring video it won't be long

play00:31

but we gotta do it why is this so boring

play00:34

well it's boring because it is

play00:36

terminological we're gonna do a lot with

play00:39

terminology right now okay so today we

play00:42

read the second chapter of a Schaeffer

play00:46

landau book and this is the chapter

play00:50

where we just get some of our terms or

play00:53

words or expressions straight so that

play00:56

we're all talking to each other and we

play00:58

know what we're talking about

play00:59

the central question is this

play01:04

are there facts that apply to everyone

play01:06

everywhere about what's right and what's

play01:09

wrong that's the central question if you

play01:13

say yes right then Schaffer Landau says

play01:19

that you are a this is his term moral

play01:26

Objectivist that view is moral

play01:30

objectivism it's the view that there are

play01:33

moral facts that apply to everyone

play01:35

everywhere no matter what they think and

play01:37

this is the view by the way that he's

play01:38

defending in the book once you land on

play01:41

that view you could ask other questions

play01:44

like another question that you might ask

play01:46

is something like

play01:50

is it the results or the products or the

play01:53

outcomes or the consequences of actions

play01:56

that make them right or wrong or is it

play01:58

something else about the actions like

play01:59

their intentions if you think it's the

play02:01

consequences if you say yes then you are

play02:05

a consequentialist and we actually

play02:08

already read a consequentialist in this

play02:12

course Bentham Andrew Bentham okay so

play02:15

that's consequentialism if you say no

play02:19

then you are some kind of

play02:22

non-consequentialist and we read a

play02:25

couple of them we read Aristotle

play02:28

Aristotle thinks that certain actions

play02:30

are virtuous or vicious but the virtue

play02:35

the goodness the moral goodness of an

play02:37

action is not determined by its

play02:40

consequences but by well some relation

play02:43

between those kinds of actions and the

play02:45

type of creature a human being that's

play02:47

performing them and then we also read we

play02:51

didn't read Conte directly but we read

play02:53

O'Neill who was characterizing Khan's

play02:55

few and Kant is also a

play02:56

non-consequentialist thinks that the

play02:58

moral rightness or wrongness of actions

play03:01

is determined by the maxim on which the

play03:04

action is founded which is not exactly

play03:05

the same as an intention but close to an

play03:08

intention okay but back up to the top

play03:10

are there objective Universal moral

play03:13

facts if you say no then you are as

play03:20

Schaffer Landau puts it a moral skeptic

play03:27

the skepticism is skepticism

play03:29

specifically about objective or

play03:32

universal moral facts you think that

play03:34

there aren't any but then there's this

play03:36

other question you say oh well if there

play03:39

are no objective moral facts you ask are

play03:43

there non objective moral facts are

play03:49

there facts about what's right and wrong

play03:51

it's just not facts that apply

play03:54

universally to everyone everywhere they

play03:56

just apply differently based on well

play03:59

some other fact about the context in

play04:02

which the action was performed if you

play04:05

say yes to this question then you're

play04:08

some kind of relativist of one kind or

play04:12

another right but actually Shafer landau

play04:15

doesn't label this position so we're

play04:17

just gonna leave this position unlabeled

play04:18

right and we're gonna ask okay so if you

play04:23

say there are no universal moral facts

play04:25

but there are non objective non

play04:28

universal moral facts then you might ask

play04:34

what fact about inaction determines

play04:37

which moral laws apply to it is it the

play04:41

day of the week that it was performed on

play04:43

is it the person who performed that

play04:46

action is it the Society of the person

play04:49

that performed that action so there are

play04:51

two typical answers to this question one

play04:55

answer is that moral facts are relative

play04:58

to the individual

play05:00

that view Schaefer landau calls well I

play05:05

don't know if he calls it moral or

play05:06

ethical he's always switching between

play05:09

moral and ethical some of these this

play05:11

might even be ethical skepticism I don't

play05:14

know we're just gonna use the word moral

play05:16

every time because it's better to be

play05:19

consistent and anytime that we say

play05:22

ethical in this course we mean the same

play05:24

thing as moral anyway so moral

play05:27

subjectivism moral subjectivism is the

play05:31

view that well there are no objective

play05:33

universal moral facts but there are some

play05:36

moral facts it's just that the moral

play05:39

facts change or are different for each

play05:42

person every person has their own moral

play05:46

code and every person's moral code is

play05:48

right for them for their own behavior

play05:52

their moral code is the one that

play05:55

determines whether what they do is right

play05:57

or wrong that's moral subjectivism now

play06:00

you might immediately think wait

play06:01

everyone has their own moral code does

play06:03

that mean that no action that anyone

play06:06

performs is wrong or immoral the answer

play06:10

is actually no some of those actions are

play06:13

going to be wrong or immoral it's just

play06:16

that the only way in action can be

play06:17

immoral is if it violates an

play06:19

individual's own moral code right so you

play06:23

personally believe that murder is wrong

play06:26

and then for some reason you murder

play06:29

someone well then that would be wrong

play06:31

but it will be wrong because you broke

play06:34

your own moral commitment or your own

play06:37

moral principle and that's the only way

play06:39

that actions can be wrong that's moral

play06:41

subjectivism the other somewhat common

play06:44

view along these lines is that the moral

play06:48

facts are relative to a different

play06:50

culture or society the idea is that

play06:56

every society has their own system of

play06:58

morality and every society system of

play07:01

morality is correct for members of that

play07:03

society so if one society practices

play07:07

human sacrifice then human sacrifice is

play07:10

morally permissible in that society for

play07:13

member

play07:14

of that society but if someone somewhere

play07:16

else does it and their society condemns

play07:18

human sacrifice then it's wrong when

play07:20

they do it right this view he just calls

play07:23

ethical or moral relativism again I know

play07:29

that he labels some of these terms with

play07:32

well he starts him with ethical instead

play07:35

of moral and some of them he starts with

play07:36

moral instead of ethical but he's using

play07:38

these terms synonymously and so I'm just

play07:39

gonna use the one term moral okay

play07:43

there's another view here there's

play07:46

another there's another answer to the

play07:48

question are there non objective moral

play07:50

facts and that answer of course is no if

play07:55

you say that there are no objective

play07:57

Universal moral facts and you say that

play08:00

there are no non objective non universal

play08:02

moral facts then you think that there

play08:03

are no moral facts at all and the name

play08:07

for this view is moral nihilism there

play08:15

are no moral facts at all that's the

play08:18

nihilistic view okay but if you go that

play08:22

route if you say that there are no moral

play08:26

truths there are no moral facts there

play08:29

are no moral laws not ones that apply to

play08:31

everyone everywhere and not ones that

play08:33

apply within a society or to individual

play08:35

people then you have this problem or a

play08:38

parent problem or at least you've got

play08:41

something you have to explain and the

play08:43

thing you have to explain is all of the

play08:45

moral talk all of the moral discourse

play08:49

all of the moral things that people say

play08:52

people say things like that's not right

play08:55

or that's evil or the right thing to do

play08:59

is law and we say this stuff a lot

play09:03

there's a lot of moral talk I don't know

play09:05

what percentage of our discourse is

play09:08

moral discourse but it's a lot I don't

play09:11

know 2% 1% that's a lot of talk that's a

play09:17

lot of what we say so what are you gonna

play09:19

say about all the moral talk if you

play09:21

answer the question are there non

play09:24

objective moral facts and are there

play09:25

objective moral facts by saying no

play09:27

there's not any

play09:27

of any kind then you have to answer the

play09:29

question can moral claims be true or

play09:39

false

play09:40

if you say yes let's go all the way down

play09:43

here if you say yes and you're a moral

play09:48

nihilist then you are what's called an

play09:53

error theorist in error theory I should

play09:56

be very very very clear is not a theory

play09:59

of morality it's a theory of moral

play10:02

language or moral talk it's the claim

play10:05

that all the moral discourse all the

play10:08

moral assertions all the moral

play10:10

statements they're all false they're all

play10:13

mistaken they're all incorrect right

play10:16

that's one route so you're a moral

play10:19

nihilist you think that there are no

play10:21

moral facts and so anytime anyone says

play10:23

anything they say that recreational drug

play10:26

use is wrong that's false it's not wrong

play10:29

recreational drug use is morally

play10:32

permissible well that's wrong also

play10:34

that's not true nothing is morally

play10:36

permissible and nothing is morally

play10:37

prohibited slavery is evil no that's

play10:42

false

play10:43

slavery is good well no that's that's

play10:46

false also right

play10:48

according to arrow Theory every time

play10:50

anyone says anything about what's

play10:53

morally right or morally wrong or

play10:55

morally permissible or morally

play10:56

impermissible every one of those

play10:59

statements is a falsehood now I should

play11:01

say something about error theories in

play11:03

general in general there's nothing wrong

play11:07

with an error theory there are lots of

play11:09

error theories that are accurate the

play11:13

example that I often get when I ask

play11:14

students in class for an example of a

play11:17

whole set of discourse a whole group of

play11:19

statements that are all just mistaken

play11:23

the whole thing is just a big mistake

play11:24

and everything they say is false

play11:26

commonly I will get the answer

play11:29

Flat Earth theory

play11:32

so the earth is roughly spherical it's

play11:36

kind of like bulges out at the sides I

play11:37

think because it's spinning and anyway

play11:40

but it's roughly spherical and so Flat

play11:43

Earth theory is false and the flat

play11:45

earthers they say all sorts of stuff

play11:47

there's all this Flat Earth discourse

play11:50

they say things like you know the photos

play11:54

of the Earth from space are doctored

play11:57

they're altered to make the earth look

play12:00

spiracle they're not real and they say

play12:04

things like and arctica is uh he's an

play12:11

ice wall right because on on the Flat

play12:14

Earth view right

play12:16

the earth is a boy here we go the earth

play12:18

is uh is flat and then here all right

play12:24

there's the Flat Earth right and in the

play12:26

middle is the North Pole they think

play12:28

where they say and then all along the

play12:31

edges is Antarctica Antarctica is just a

play12:34

huge ice wall around the edges and

play12:36

that's why we can't go to the edge of

play12:39

the earth because it's just too cold and

play12:40

everybody tries to go and and they just

play12:42

give up or something because it's really

play12:45

cold um and they think that the Sun and

play12:47

the moon

play12:48

okay the Sun and Moon orbit like like

play12:57

not like hawks but like like birds of

play13:00

prey circling a wounded animal flying

play13:03

around it from above I don't know I'm

play13:08

gonna say hawks but I know Hawks don't

play13:10

do that it's some other kind of bird of

play13:12

prey sorry Hawks um anyway the Sun in

play13:15

the moon they just sort of like go

play13:16

around in circles on top you know

play13:19

there's the moon and the Sun and they go

play13:20

like this anyway they say all these

play13:23

things what is the correct theory of all

play13:28

of this Flat Earth discourse all of

play13:30

these statements the right theory I'll

play13:32

just put it out there is an error theory

play13:36

they're all false it's a whole big

play13:39

mistake all this whole there's all

play13:40

theories just one mistake it's one big

play13:43

error and every single statement that

play13:45

they

play13:45

make is a falsehood false false false

play13:50

that's an error theory the error

play13:53

theorists in this case says that just

play13:56

about every moral statement and moral

play14:00

statements of course are way more common

play14:02

than flat earther statements so that's

play14:04

what the error theorist says but you

play14:07

might want to keep those moral

play14:09

statements around you might think no no

play14:12

that's not right

play14:12

when we make moral statements we're not

play14:15

even saying anything that can be true or

play14:19

false

play14:20

in the first place and therefore we can

play14:24

keep saying all of these moral things if

play14:27

that's your view if your answer here is

play14:31

no you say that moral claims aren't even

play14:34

the kind of thing that could be true or

play14:36

false in the first place well then you

play14:40

are some kind of non cognitive assist

play14:47

you think that moral statements don't

play14:50

literally have cognitive significance

play14:53

they don't state propositions right we

play14:55

read a Jair a Jair fits into this

play14:59

category

play14:59

he's a non cognitive estate who we've

play15:04

laid out the terminological territory

play15:07

are their objective universal moral

play15:09

facts if you say yes then you're a moral

play15:13

Objectivist and then there's this

play15:15

further question well do those moral

play15:17

facts depend fundamentally or primarily

play15:20

or exclusively on the consequences of

play15:23

actions if the answer is yes then you're

play15:25

a consequentialist like Bentham if the

play15:27

answer is no then you're a

play15:28

non-consequentialist like Aristotle or

play15:30

can't if instead to this first question

play15:34

you say no there are no objective

play15:37

Universal moral facts then you're a

play15:39

moral skeptic and then the question is

play15:41

well are there non objective non

play15:43

universal moral facts if the answer is

play15:45

yes then you're either a relativist if

play15:47

you think the moral facts are different

play15:49

for every society or you're a

play15:51

subjectivist if you think that the moral

play15:53

facts are different for every person

play15:55

but if instead

play15:57

you say no there are no moral facts at

play16:00

all there are no objective moral facts

play16:02

and there are no relative moral facts

play16:05

there just are no moral facts there are

play16:07

no moral laws nothing is strictly

play16:10

speaking morally good and nothing is

play16:13

morally bad then you're a nihilist and

play16:15

then you have to explain moral discourse

play16:18

and either you explain that discourse by

play16:20

saying it's all false in which case

play16:22

you're an error theorist or you explain

play16:25

that discourse all of that moral talk by

play16:27

saying that that talk was never the kind

play16:29

of thing that could be true or false in

play16:30

the first place it is for instance just

play16:33

a bunch of ways of expressing a

play16:37

sentiment like saying boo or yay all

play16:40

right that is the moral territory and it

play16:44

might seem like this has been a rather

play16:47

boring chapter that just layed out the

play16:51

moral territory and that's true it was a

play16:54

rather boring chapter that laid out the

play16:57

moral territory or the moral landscape

play16:59

but there was a little bit of an

play17:02

argument that was snuck in there a

play17:05

little bit of an argument against moral

play17:09

skepticism or a kind of defense of moral

play17:14

objectivism okay

play17:15

here's what that argument is the

play17:18

argument comes in the form of a

play17:20

distinction between vocabulary on the

play17:25

one hand and facts or entities entities

play17:33

on the other hand here's an example of

play17:37

some vocabulary the word planet we made

play17:43

that up the word we made up the word

play17:45

planet that's uncontroversial everyone

play17:48

thinks that we invented the word planet

play17:51

we made it up and we made up similar

play17:53

words in other languages those are human

play17:55

inventions words vocabulary but then

play17:58

there's the actual things right the

play18:02

planets themselves yeah it was like a

play18:06

on the planet another thing

play18:09

they're the planets themselves we didn't

play18:13

make those those were out there long

play18:15

before we got here and the sentences

play18:18

that we construct with vocabulary right

play18:22

we say Venus is aa

play18:27

planet those sentences well those are

play18:31

human creations also we say the

play18:34

sentences we made up the words and then

play18:36

we use these words that we made up to

play18:38

make more things like sentences which

play18:40

are a bunch of air waves that come out

play18:42

of our mouths or a bunch of bits of ink

play18:44

that we write on surfaces of various

play18:47

kinds right this is all stuff that we

play18:49

make but the fact the entities

play18:53

themselves the planets and then the

play18:55

facts about those planets like the fact

play18:59

that Venus is a planet

play19:01

well that's just a fact we didn't make

play19:03

that fact up venus was a planet long

play19:06

before we got here there it was circling

play19:09

the Sun every two hundred in something

play19:12

days I don't know how long Venus takes

play19:14

to go around the Sun but I know it's 200

play19:17

something days it's less than 300 days

play19:18

takes us 365 it takes Venus to something

play19:22

right Venus goes around the Sun there it

play19:25

was orbiting the Sun all this while

play19:28

before we got around here so Venus was a

play19:31

planet long Venus existed and Venus was

play19:33

a planet long before we got here and

play19:35

started making up words so the facts

play19:38

they're out there independent of us and

play19:41

the entities the planet it's out there

play19:44

independent of us right but the words

play19:47

and the sentences we made those why does

play19:51

Schafer Landau draw this distinction he

play19:54

draws this distinction to point

play19:56

something out which is that it's sort of

play19:58

obvious to a lot of people that we've

play20:00

created these things and they mistakenly

play20:03

go from the fact that we invented the

play20:06

words or the vocabulary to the fact that

play20:09

we invented the things we didn't invent

play20:12

the things at least not some of them

play20:14

right I mean some things we did invent

play20:16

so here's another entity a

play20:19

table here's the table and there's the

play20:23

legs and like right there right we

play20:27

invented tables someone I didn't do it

play20:29

someone invented the table and then

play20:31

we've been making tables ever since we

play20:33

make tons of tables and we also made the

play20:35

word table so sometimes we make the word

play20:40

and we make the thing but sometimes we

play20:43

just make the word and we don't make the

play20:44

thing so the mere fact that we invented

play20:48

the terminology and we uttered the

play20:51

sentences the mere fact that all of this

play20:53

comes from us and wasn't out there

play20:55

independently of us it doesn't mean that

play20:59

these things aren't out there

play21:01

independently of us some of these things

play21:03

are out there independent of us and so

play21:06

what Shaffer Landau is gonna claim is

play21:09

that yeah sure

play21:10

we invented the terms right and wrong we

play21:17

invented terms like good and evil but

play21:20

then it's just still a further question

play21:21

of whether or not we invented goodness

play21:25

or evilness also if we did invent that

play21:28

too

play21:29

then we are at least some kind of moral

play21:31

skeptic where you ought to be a moral

play21:33

skeptic rather if we invented goodness

play21:36

itself or badness itself but don't

play21:41

mistakenly assume that just because we

play21:45

invented the word right and the word

play21:48

wrong that we also thereby made those

play21:52

kinds of behavior right or wrong or that

play21:55

we just made up the fact that certain

play21:57

kinds of behavior are right or wrong

play22:06

you

Rate This
โ˜…
โ˜…
โ˜…
โ˜…
โ˜…

5.0 / 5 (0 votes)

Related Tags
Moral PhilosophyEthical DebatesObjectivismRelativismSkepticismConsequentialismMoral FactsEthical TheoriesMoral LanguageError Theory