Pro-Choice Arguments

Wes McMichael
1 Sept 202315:00

Summary

TLDRThe script explores two pro-choice arguments on abortion. The first, 'right to life does not generate obligation,' is illustrated by Judith Jarvis Thompson's thought experiment, suggesting a woman is not morally obligated to sustain a fetus's life. The second argument, 'no valuable future,' posits that fetuses lack unified consciousness, making abortion not as wrong as killing a person. Challenges to these views are also discussed, emphasizing the complexity of the abortion debate.

Takeaways

  • ๐Ÿ“š The speaker introduces two pro-choice arguments: one that abortion is permissible even if the fetus has a right to life, and another that fetuses do not have a right to life.
  • ๐Ÿค” The 'right to life does not generate obligation' argument challenges the assumption that if a fetus has a right to life, it obligates others to sustain it.
  • ๐ŸŽป Judith Jarvis Thompson's 'violinist' thought experiment is used to illustrate that one's right to life does not impose an obligation on another to use their body to sustain that life.
  • ๐Ÿคฐ The argument suggests that a woman's consent to sex does not equate to consent to pregnancy, challenging the idea that she has a special obligation to a fetus.
  • ๐Ÿšซ The 'no V-flow' argument posits that killing is wrong because it takes away a valuable future, which is not present in zygotes, embryos, and fetuses due to the lack of unified consciousness.
  • ๐Ÿง  The unified consciousness, which is necessary for valuing a future, is not present in early stages of fetal development, suggesting that abortion at these stages is not morally wrong in the same way as killing a person.
  • ๐Ÿคทโ€โ™€๏ธ The speaker acknowledges that while abortion may not be wrong because of the 'wrongness of killing,' it can be wrong for other reasons, such as cruelty or an inappropriate understanding of motherhood.
  • ๐Ÿ‘ถ The argument does not prove that killing a zygote, embryo, or fetus is morally acceptable, but rather that it is not wrong in the same way as killing a person with a unified consciousness.
  • ๐Ÿ’ก The speaker concludes that abortion can be morally complex and context-dependent, with potential wrongness arising from factors other than the act of killing a fetus.

Q & A

  • What is the main argument presented by Judith Jarvis Thompson in her paper on abortion?

    -Judith Jarvis Thompson argues that even if fetuses have a right to life, it does not necessarily create an obligation for a pregnant woman to sustain that life. This is based on the premise that a right to life does not generate a right to someone else's body to sustain that life.

  • What is the 'violinist argument' and how does it relate to the discussion on abortion?

    -The 'violinist argument' is a thought experiment by Judith Jarvis Thompson where she imagines a scenario where a person wakes up attached to a famous violinist to save their life. The argument suggests that even though the violinist has a right to life, it doesn't morally obligate the person to sustain the violinist's life against their will, thus paralleling the idea that a pregnant woman should not be obligated to carry a fetus to term.

  • How does Thompson's argument apply to cases of rape?

    -Thompson's argument is particularly relevant to cases of rape because it suggests that the woman did not willingly or knowingly create a life and therefore should not have a special obligation to sustain the life of the fetus. The 'violinist argument' is used to illustrate that being connected to another life without consent does not impose a moral obligation to continue sustaining it.

  • What is the counterargument to Thompson's 'right to life does not generate obligation' argument?

    -One counterargument is that by engaging in sexual intercourse, a woman understands the potential consequences, including the creation of a life, and thus may have a special obligation to that life. This suggests that the act of sex implies a tacit agreement to the potential responsibilities that come with it.

  • What is the 'no V flow argument' and how does it relate to the moral permissibility of abortion?

    -The 'no V flow argument' posits that killing is wrong because it takes away a valuable future, which is only possessed by beings with unified consciousness. Since zygotes, embryos, and fetuses lack this unified consciousness, it is argued that killing them does not deprive them of a valuable future like ours, and therefore, abortion may not be morally wrong in the same way as killing a person with unified consciousness.

  • How does the concept of 'unified consciousness' play a role in the 'no V flow argument'?

    -In the 'no V flow argument', 'unified consciousness' is used to differentiate between beings that have a valuable future and those that do not. It is suggested that only beings with this consciousness can value anything, and since fetuses do not exhibit organized brain activity indicative of unified consciousness until a certain stage of development, their destruction does not carry the same moral weight as killing a person with such consciousness.

  • What is the potential issue with the 'no V flow argument' as it pertains to infanticide?

    -The potential issue with the 'no V flow argument' is that if it is accepted that the absence of unified consciousness justifies the permissibility of abortion, it could also be used to argue for the permissibility of infanticide, which is generally considered morally wrong. This highlights a possible inconsistency in the argument's application.

  • How does the speaker suggest that abortion might be wrong in ways other than the wrongness of killing?

    -The speaker suggests that abortion might be wrong due to factors such as a person's lack of an appropriate sense of awe, acting cruelly, wrongly assessing the value of motherhood, or having an inappropriate understanding of disabilities. These factors could make an abortion decision morally questionable, even if the act of killing a fetus is not inherently wrong.

  • What is the speaker's conclusion regarding the morality of abortion based on their dissertation?

    -The speaker concludes that abortion is not inherently wrong because killing zygotes, fetuses, or embryos is wrong, but it can often be wrong for other reasons, which may vary on a case-by-case basis. They also mention that sometimes, not having an abortion might be wrong if bringing a child into existence would cause significant hardship.

  • What is the significance of the speaker's mention of the potential moral obligations of a doctor who gives a drug to a violinist?

    -The speaker uses the example of a doctor who gives a drug to a violinist to illustrate that creating a dependency or ensuring someone's life does not automatically impose an ongoing obligation to sustain that life. This is relevant to the discussion on abortion as it challenges the idea that a woman who becomes pregnant has a moral obligation to continue the pregnancy simply because she was responsible for the conception.

Outlines

00:00

๐Ÿค” The Permissibility of Abortion Despite Fetal Rights

The paragraph discusses two types of pro-choice arguments regarding abortion. The first argument, called the 'right to life does not generate obligation' argument, suggests that even if a fetus has a right to life, it does not impose an obligation on others to sustain that life. The speaker references Judith Jarvis Thompson's influential paper, which challenges the assumption that a right to life inherently creates a duty not to kill. Thompson introduces a thought experiment involving a violinist to illustrate her point that one's right to life does not equate to a right to another's body or resources. The argument is nuanced, considering cases of rape and the implications of consent and autonomy in the context of pregnancy.

05:02

๐Ÿ‘ถ Autonomy and the Limits of Obligation in Pregnancy

This paragraph delves into the implications of the 'right to life does not generate obligation' argument, specifically addressing theๅฐๆ็ดๅฎถ' thought experiment. The speaker argues that the violinist's right to life does not morally obligate an unwilling individual to be connected to them for an extended period. The discussion extends to the idea that a woman's decision to have sex does not equate to a consent to bear a child, drawing parallels to other situations where consent can be withdrawn. The paragraph also raises the question of whether creating a life gives one a special obligation to sustain it, using the example of a doctor who saves a life but is not obligated to provide ongoing life support.

10:04

๐Ÿง  The Lack of a Valuable Future in Early Stages of Life

The final paragraph presented introduces the 'no valuable future flow' argument, which posits that killing is wrong because it deprives an individual of a valuable future. The argument is applied to zygotes, embryos, and fetuses, suggesting that since they lack unified consciousness, their destruction does not deprive them of a valuable future. The speaker discusses the biological perspective that cells are regularly replaced in the body, but it is the unified consciousness that gives value to life. The paragraph concludes by suggesting that while abortion may not be wrong because of the lack of wrongness in killing at early stages, it can still be wrong for other reasons, such as cruelty or a lack of appreciation for the value of life.

Mindmap

Keywords

๐Ÿ’กPro-choice

Pro-choice refers to the belief that a woman has the right to choose whether or not to have an abortion. In the video, the presenter discusses pro-choice arguments, emphasizing the debate around the moral and legal aspects of abortion. The term is central to the video's theme as it sets the stage for exploring different philosophical perspectives on abortion rights.

๐Ÿ’กRight to life

The 'right to life' is a philosophical and legal principle suggesting that every individual has an inherent right to live. In the context of the video, it is used to explore the argument that even if a fetus has a right to life, it does not necessarily impose an obligation on a woman to sustain that life, challenging traditional pro-life stances.

๐Ÿ’กViolinist argument

The 'violinist argument' is a thought experiment introduced by Judith Jarvis Thompson to illustrate the concept that having a right to life does not automatically confer a right to another person's body. In the video, this argument is used to support the idea that a woman's body autonomy should not be compromised by the life of a fetus, even if it is assumed to have a right to life.

๐Ÿ’กAutonomy

Autonomy in the video refers to an individual's right to self-governance, particularly in decisions regarding their own body. It is a key concept in the discussion of abortion rights, as it emphasizes the importance of a woman's control over her own body and life choices, independent of any obligations to a fetus.

๐Ÿ’กUnified consciousness

Unified consciousness is a concept used in the video to describe the coherent and continuous sense of self-awareness that is typically associated with personhood. The argument suggests that since fetuses lack this unified consciousness, their potential for a valuable future like ours is not present, and thus, the moral wrongness of killing (in the traditional sense) does not apply to them.

๐Ÿ’กZygote, embryo, and fetus

These terms refer to different stages of prenatal development: a zygote is a fertilized egg, an embryo is the early developmental stage, and a fetus is the later stage before birth. The video discusses these stages to argue that at certain points, they may not possess the unified consciousness necessary for the moral considerations typically associated with personhood.

๐Ÿ’กMoral obligation

Moral obligation is a duty or responsibility that an individual feels compelled to fulfill based on ethical principles. In the video, it is discussed in the context of whether a woman has a moral obligation to carry a pregnancy to term, even if it is argued that the fetus has a right to life.

๐Ÿ’กPersonhood

Personhood is a concept that refers to the status of being a person, often associated with rights and moral considerations. The video explores the debate over when a fetus attains personhood and whether this attainment should influence the moral and legal considerations of abortion.

๐Ÿ’กConsent

Consent in the video is discussed in the context of sexual activity and the implications it may have for the moral obligations regarding pregnancy. It is used to argue that even if a woman consents to sex, which could lead to pregnancy, it does not necessarily mean she has consented to carry the child to term.

๐Ÿ’กHardship

Hardship in the video refers to the potential difficulties or suffering that might be caused by bringing a child into existence. The presenter suggests that in some cases, the hardship associated with having a child might make it morally justifiable not to have an abortion, challenging the idea that abortion is always wrong.

Highlights

Introduction of two pro-choice arguments: one posits that abortion is permissible even if the fetus has a right to life, and the other argues that abortion is permissible because fetuses don't have a right to life.

The 'right to life does not generate obligation' argument challenges the assumption that if fetuses have a right to life, there is a duty not to kill them.

Judith Jarvis Thompson's influential paper on abortion, which introduced a new perspective on the debate.

The 'violinist' thought experiment by Thompson to illustrate the argument that a right to life does not impose an obligation on others to sustain that life.

Critique of the violinist argument, suggesting it may apply more to cases of rape where the pregnancy was not consented to.

Argument that consent to sex does not equate to consent to pregnancy, using the analogy of a money clip left on a table.

Discussion on whether previous decisions, like consenting to sex, create an obligation to carry a child.

The 'no V-flow' argument, which claims that killing is wrong because it takes away a valuable future, but fetuses lack the unified consciousness to have such a future.

Biological perspective on the 'no V-flow' argument, noting that cells in the human body are replaced but the unified consciousness persists.

Challenge to the 'no V-flow' argument, pointing out that it might not be wrong to kill a zygote, embryo, or fetus, but this does not mean it is morally right.

The potential for abortion to be wrong not because killing a fetus is wrong, but for other reasons such as cruelty or inappropriate valuation of life.

The possibility that not having an abortion could be wrong if bringing a child into existence would cause significant hardship.

Conclusion that abortion is not inherently wrong because of the act of killing a fetus, but can be wrong for various other reasons on a case-by-case basis.

The importance of considering the context and individual circumstances when evaluating the morality of abortion.

Transcripts

play00:00

I'm going to present to you two kinds of

play00:03

pro-choice arguments still just two

play00:04

arguments like I did with the pro-life

play00:06

but two kinds and I'm gonna call the

play00:08

first the abortion is permissible even

play00:10

if the fetus has a right to life

play00:12

argument I'm going to call it the right

play00:14

to life does not generate obligation

play00:15

argument still not a good name uh but

play00:18

that's what I'm gonna call it and then

play00:19

I'm going to talk about the idea that

play00:21

abortion is permissible because fetuses

play00:24

don't have a right to life so one says

play00:26

that even if fetuses have a right to

play00:27

life abortion is still okay and the

play00:30

other says that um abortion is okay

play00:32

because fetuses do not have a right to

play00:35

life so let me talk about the first one

play00:37

uh first the right to life does not

play00:39

generate an obligation argument and what

play00:41

I'm really doing here is I'm taking the

play00:44

idea of an argument by a very famous uh

play00:47

pro-life argument by Judith Jarvis

play00:49

Thompson she had a really interesting

play00:51

paper I think it was 74 but it might

play00:53

have been a little before that I'm not

play00:54

sure

play00:55

um but a really interesting paper on

play00:58

abortion what everybody had been doing

play01:00

to that point is arguing over whether or

play01:03

not fetuses have a right to life and

play01:05

that it was just assumed that if fetuses

play01:07

have a right to life then there's an

play01:10

obligation not to there's a duty not to

play01:12

kill them

play01:14

um and

play01:15

uh Thompson

play01:17

agreed that fetuses did not have a right

play01:20

to lie but she said well what if I

play01:22

assumed for the sake of argument that

play01:24

fetuses do have a right to life I think

play01:27

even if I assume that which I don't

play01:29

believe I can argue that abortion is

play01:32

still permissible and so she comes out

play01:35

with this uh article and it really

play01:38

changed a lot of the way that people

play01:40

thought about abortion especially in

play01:42

cases of rape

play01:43

um

play01:44

but it had kind of long reaching effects

play01:48

people's when you read on abortion

play01:51

um it will always be included in that

play01:54

discussion this article this argument

play01:57

um you might have heard it referred to

play01:59

as the violinist argument and you'll see

play02:01

why in a little bit but let me just kind

play02:03

of give you the version of it uh what

play02:04

she says it's not exactly how she puts

play02:06

it but something like this

play02:08

um the right to life does not generate

play02:10

an obligation argument so the argument

play02:13

goes something like this a right to life

play02:15

does not generate a an obligation

play02:19

um for someone else to say in that life

play02:21

or the way I have it in my notes a right

play02:23

to life does not generate a right to

play02:25

someone else's body to sustain that life

play02:27

so if you have a right to life that

play02:28

doesn't mean you have a right to

play02:30

somebody else's body in order to sustain

play02:32

that life or anything that has a right

play02:34

to life doesn't have necessarily have a

play02:37

right to use somebody else's body to

play02:39

sustain that life so that's the first

play02:41

premise the second premise it just says

play02:43

so even if a fetus has a right to life

play02:46

it does not follow that a pregnant woman

play02:48

has an obligation to offer her body to

play02:51

sustain that life so she says a right to

play02:53

life does not generate an obligation for

play02:56

somebody else to sustain that life so

play02:58

even if a fetus has a right to life it

play03:01

doesn't create an obligation on a

play03:02

pregnant woman to sustain that life

play03:04

how does she support this really

play03:06

interesting thought experiment she's

play03:07

she's great or she was great she passed

play03:09

away unfortunately she was great about

play03:12

these cool thought experiments and weird

play03:15

thought experiments that she has in this

play03:16

particular article has a lot of very

play03:18

strange ones and that wasn't the only in

play03:20

her career either but

play03:22

um so she has one of the weird thought

play03:24

experiments that she has is called the

play03:26

violinist argument and what she says is

play03:29

imagine that you and it's important

play03:31

that's you it's nobody else it's you go

play03:33

to sleep tonight and you wake up and you

play03:37

find yourself attached to all these

play03:38

medical tubes and stuff like this

play03:40

remember this in the 70s

play03:42

um to a famous violinist a very good

play03:45

violinist overnight the society for

play03:48

Musicians music lovers

play03:50

um discovered that

play03:52

the violinist was definitely ill and

play03:57

um only you would be a match for

play04:00

sustaining that violinist life and so

play04:02

they attached to these tubes and if you

play04:05

stay there for nine months and let that

play04:08

person's blood pass through your kidneys

play04:09

or whatever however it works your body

play04:12

keeps them alive nine months then he'll

play04:14

be okay and he can be separated at that

play04:16

time

play04:18

jar uh Thompson argues that it's not

play04:22

clear that the violinists right to life

play04:25

which he clearly has a right to life

play04:26

just like you and me the violinist has a

play04:28

right to life it's not clear that that

play04:30

violinist right to life

play04:32

um creates an obligation on you to

play04:34

sustain that life it's nice of you to do

play04:37

that it would be great of you to stay

play04:39

hooked up to that guy for nine months

play04:40

and and

play04:42

um get him better but you have things to

play04:43

do right you have families and stuff

play04:45

like that

play04:47

um and if nine months just sounds like

play04:49

well okay yeah that's that sucks but I

play04:51

would do it uh she said well extend that

play04:53

then say it's nine years right she was

play04:55

May say nine months because it was

play04:58

um the the idea of pregnancy to say it

play05:01

was nine years

play05:03

um

play05:04

you know I have grandkids and um and

play05:07

people in my life that I and I got a job

play05:09

and all of those things and I can't be

play05:11

strapped to this person for nine years

play05:14

um it would be nice of me true and nice

play05:17

of you true to stay hooked up to this

play05:20

person but you have goals you're at

play05:22

college presumably because you have a

play05:23

goal of graduating and working and doing

play05:25

all those things and you can't do that

play05:27

attached to this person and so the idea

play05:31

here with the violin is now again you

play05:33

might think there's a difference between

play05:34

nine months nine years and all that kind

play05:36

of stuff but again the idea is that just

play05:38

because

play05:39

we could keep extending that 90 years

play05:41

whatever you want but at some point I

play05:44

think most people would agree that that

play05:47

person's right to life

play05:49

while it's real doesn't override your

play05:53

right to autonomy to choose what to do

play05:55

with your body that you don't have to

play05:58

you know it's nice of you it's great of

play06:00

you to stay hooked up to the person but

play06:03

it's not required morally required for

play06:06

you to do that it would be a good thing

play06:07

for you to do that but it's not morally

play06:10

required that's the idea think about 20

play06:13

years or whatever again the violinist

play06:16

has a right to life but it's not clear

play06:17

that you have a obligation to sustain

play06:19

that life now

play06:23

so it the the violentist example is

play06:26

supposed to just prove that point that

play06:28

one point that's all it's supposed to do

play06:30

the violence example is supposed to

play06:31

prove that a right to life doesn't

play06:33

create an obligation on somebody else to

play06:35

sustain it and she has these other

play06:36

things that are really interesting you

play06:38

know so like

play06:39

um she said she has a sickness that only

play06:42

the cool Touch of Henry Fonda you

play06:44

wouldn't know that uh updated with I

play06:46

don't know Chris Pine probably for most

play06:49

of you that's uh all the Chris's are too

play06:52

old too but whoever Harry Styles whoever

play06:56

kids these days like I don't know right

play06:58

uh you know just even if it's only his

play07:03

healing touch only his touch on his head

play07:04

uh on your head would heal you it would

play07:07

be nice of that person to travel across

play07:09

the United States and touch you on the

play07:11

head but they don't have an obligation

play07:13

to do that right so a right to life

play07:15

doesn't necessarily create an obligation

play07:17

on somebody else that's just to sustain

play07:19

your life now a problem for this is

play07:22

probably obvious to you

play07:23

um people say look a woman who has

play07:26

intercourse understands that intercourse

play07:29

can lead sex can lead to the generation

play07:32

of a life and they argue that because

play07:34

the woman through her actions generated

play07:38

the life she has a special obligation to

play07:39

that life and the violinist case if it

play07:42

is successful at all would apply in

play07:45

cases of rape right because uh you went

play07:47

to sleep and were plugged into it

play07:48

against your will so um that would be in

play07:52

the case of pregnancy because of rape

play07:54

that would make sense because that

play07:56

person's right to life the fetus is

play07:57

Right to Life you didn't do anything

play07:59

consciously that created that life and

play08:01

so you don't have any special

play08:02

obligations to it right

play08:04

um so some people have pointed out that

play08:07

it makes a lot of sense in the case of

play08:09

rape but maybe not in anything else now

play08:11

there are some responses to that too uh

play08:13

for one thing it's not clear that

play08:15

agreeing to have sex with somebody is

play08:17

agreeing to carry a child if one is

play08:18

produced

play08:20

um so imagine so I always have a problem

play08:22

uh with my wallet in my pocket you know

play08:26

it hurts my back and something like that

play08:27

and so say instead of carrying wallets I

play08:29

carry money clips and I just so happen

play08:31

to have gone to the bank to because we

play08:33

send money to Peru and I have a ton of

play08:35

money that I don't usually have in my

play08:36

wallet right now but and so it's really

play08:38

thick and heavy and it's not usually

play08:40

thick and heavy I don't usually carry a

play08:42

lot of money around but anyway it has a

play08:45

lot and it hurts my back right and let's

play08:46

say that I didn't have a while I just

play08:48

had a money clip and so I just put it on

play08:50

the table and um that's usually what we

play08:52

do you know at a restaurant when we

play08:54

leave a tip and I walk away and realize

play08:57

oh no I didn't mean to do that and so um

play09:00

just because I put money on the table

play09:02

and forgot to pick it up it might be

play09:03

uncomfortable

play09:05

um for me to go back and and tell a

play09:07

waiter no that's not your tip I need it

play09:09

back but it doesn't seem like just

play09:11

because I made a decision like that when

play09:14

I didn't intend to give it uh just

play09:16

because I because I didn't intend to

play09:19

give it as tip it doesn't mean now I'm

play09:20

obligated to go through with it so a

play09:23

person who has sex and doesn't intend

play09:26

um to have a child it doesn't seem like

play09:28

that should obligate them then to go

play09:31

through with that

play09:33

um also it's not clear that one a person

play09:35

signs away their autonomy by previous

play09:37

decisions so I need to come up with a

play09:40

better example of this I apologize if

play09:42

this offends anybody and this one was on

play09:45

my mind because I watched this

play09:46

documentary on porn and um and they one

play09:51

of the scenes was really really brutal

play09:53

and the camera people like walked away

play09:55

from it

play09:56

um

play09:57

because it was supposed to be this

play09:59

violent scene but anyway so let's say

play10:01

that there's a porn actress who agrees

play10:03

consents to uh a like rough stimulated

play10:08

um violent uh sex act

play10:11

um but then as she's going through with

play10:13

it

play10:14

um says you know what this is too much I

play10:15

mean I saw the videos and you guys told

play10:17

me were honest with me what was going on

play10:19

but this is just too much it brings up

play10:20

too many memories or whatever I don't

play10:22

want to do it right it's not like you

play10:25

can say no you committed to doing this

play10:27

and so you know we're gonna do whatever

play10:29

that that would be rape right

play10:32

um at that point

play10:33

so even though she agreed and consented

play10:35

to it at the time you know she could

play10:37

lose her contractual obligations and all

play10:39

that kind of stuff right but what she

play10:40

did but just because she agreed to it

play10:43

doesn't mean that she has an obligation

play10:45

then to go through it so even if

play10:47

somebody was having sex with the

play10:49

intention of having a child it doesn't

play10:51

seem like that creates an obligation for

play10:54

them then to go through with having a

play10:56

child because maybe once she experiences

play10:58

it maybe the situations have changed

play11:01

um maybe a partner's left or something

play11:04

like that

play11:05

um maybe once she experienced it says no

play11:07

this was more than I handle uh I I you

play11:10

know took into account just like the the

play11:13

porn actress and so it doesn't look like

play11:14

our commitments beforehand always create

play11:17

an obligation to follow through with

play11:18

those right and then lastly a problem

play11:20

that says it's not clear that one has an

play11:23

obligation to provide for another

play11:24

another person's needs when they're

play11:26

responsible for that person's existence

play11:28

so we say hey there's a special

play11:29

obligation the mom you know she had sex

play11:31

and so you know she knew what could

play11:34

happen but even if we are responsible

play11:37

for somebody being alive it doesn't seem

play11:40

that we do in many cases have an

play11:43

obligation to sustain that life right so

play11:46

imagine that there is a doctor who gives

play11:50

the violinist a drug that will keep him

play11:52

alive for 10 years but after he'll need

play11:54

the doctor's kidneys and only the

play11:56

doctor's kidneys it doesn't seem like

play11:58

the doctor would be obligated then to

play12:00

give that person use of the kidneys even

play12:02

though he's responsible for him being

play12:04

alive because he gave him the drug right

play12:05

and so just

play12:07

um just

play12:09

giving the person life or ensuring that

play12:11

they had life doesn't seem like you have

play12:13

an obligation to sustain that life all

play12:15

right so that is uh kind of Thompson's

play12:17

argument and some problems and some

play12:19

ideas about that I'm going to try to say

play12:21

a little bit or get started on the no V

play12:24

flow argument so the no V flow argument

play12:27

goes from Marcus's argument because I

play12:29

think there's something right about it

play12:30

right

play12:31

and it says killing is wrong because it

play12:33

takes away one's valuable future like

play12:34

ours

play12:35

only the second premise only something

play12:37

with the unified Consciousness has a

play12:39

valuable future like ours zygotes

play12:41

embryos and fetuses do not have a

play12:43

unified Consciousness therefore killing

play12:45

zygous and embryos and fetuses does not

play12:46

take away a valuable future like ours

play12:48

and so it doesn't capture the wrongness

play12:50

of killing so there's nothing wrong with

play12:52

it doesn't say there's something right

play12:53

with it just says there's nothing wrong

play12:54

with uh killing them and for support of

play12:57

this somebody might point out that

play12:58

biology doesn't have a v flow like we

play13:00

talked about before every cell in the

play13:02

human body I think maybe there's a

play13:04

couple that are sticky but most every

play13:06

cell in the human body is replaced

play13:07

several times within an average life

play13:09

what survives though is that unified

play13:11

Consciousness that Consciousness that

play13:13

you see yourself as an individual as as

play13:16

a whole and that's the only thing that

play13:19

can value anything at all and so that's

play13:21

the only thing that has a valuable

play13:22

future the brain can't sustain a unified

play13:25

Consciousness in a zygote embryo fetus

play13:28

there's no organized brain activity you

play13:30

don't see Alpha Beta delta waves until

play13:32

about 25 to 32 weeks depending on

play13:35

um and there's no clear indication of a

play13:38

unified Consciousness until at least 18

play13:41

months after birth now that creates a

play13:43

whole other problem right

play13:45

um so uh it looks like the romness of

play13:48

killing isn't in that right and so it

play13:51

wouldn't be wrong to have an abortion

play13:54

because the wrongness of killing

play13:56

um the conditions for the wrongness of

play13:58

killing aren't there this unified

play13:59

Consciousness now uh this doesn't prove

play14:02

the problem for this is that it doesn't

play14:04

prove that killing a zygote embryo fetus

play14:06

is okay it's just not wrong in the same

play14:08

way as a killing other uh things it

play14:11

might even work against

play14:14

infanticide you might have to this might

play14:17

say that infanticide is okay which seems

play14:19

obviously wrong so let me just say

play14:21

quickly my conclusion for what it's

play14:22

worth which is worth nothing abortion

play14:24

doesn't seem to be wrong because killing

play14:26

zygos fetuses or embryos is wrong but

play14:29

can and often is wrong in other ways

play14:31

maybe on a case-by-case uh basis uh this

play14:34

is what my whole dissertation was about

play14:36

that sometimes it might be that a person

play14:38

doesn't have an appropriate sense of awe

play14:39

that they could be acting cruelly that

play14:41

they could wrongly assess the value

play14:42

value of motherhood that if they have an

play14:44

inappropriate understanding of

play14:45

disabilities or something like that

play14:48

um sometimes even if even if it's wrong

play14:51

not it might be wrong not to have an

play14:53

abortion when bringing a child into uh

play14:56

existence would bring a great hardship

play14:58

okay that's all I have time for sorry

Rate This
โ˜…
โ˜…
โ˜…
โ˜…
โ˜…

5.0 / 5 (0 votes)

Related Tags
Abortion EthicsPro-ChoiceRight to LifePhilosophical DebateEthical DilemmaFetus RightsAutonomyJudith Jarvis ThompsonViolinist ArgumentConsciousness