Intro to Consequentialism & Act Utilitarianism

Wes McMichael
14 Jun 202211:49

Summary

TLDRThis video script delves into normative ethical theories, focusing on consequentialism, also known as utilitarianism. It discusses the concept that the morality of an action is determined by its outcomes, with the aim to maximize happiness. The script introduces utilitarianism's principle of utility, advocating for actions that bring the greatest happiness to the greatest number. It contrasts this with other ethical theories like deontology and virtue ethics, highlighting the debate between these approaches. The speaker also raises critical questions about utilitarianism's alignment with our moral intuitions, suggesting potential conflicts and inviting further exploration in subsequent discussions.

Takeaways

  • πŸ” The discussion shifts from the foundations of morality to normative ethical theories, focusing on how to make morally right decisions in everyday life.
  • πŸ“Š Consequentialism, also known as utilitarianism, is a popular ethical theory where the morality of an act is determined solely by its consequences.
  • πŸ€” The script introduces three main ethical theories: consequentialism, deontological ethics (conscient ethics), and virtue ethics, with consequentialism being the starting point.
  • πŸ‘¨β€πŸ« The lecturer contrasts their personal virtue ethics stance with their wife's consequentialism, highlighting the practical implications of these theories in daily life.
  • πŸ“š The early proponents of utilitarianism, Jeremy Bentham and John Stuart Mill, are mentioned, with Bentham's influence on modern prison systems noted.
  • 🌟 Utilitarianism is based on the principle of utility, which posits that one should choose the action that maximizes happiness in any given situation.
  • πŸ”’ Hedonistic act utilitarianism, a type of utilitarianism, is discussed, emphasizing the importance of happiness and suffering in moral decision-making.
  • πŸ“ Three principles of hedonistic act utilitarianism are outlined: actions are judged by their consequences, happiness is the key factor in assessing consequences, and everyone's happiness is equally important.
  • 🀝 The theory suggests a moral obligation to improve the world, aligning with the intuitive belief that morality involves promoting well-being and reducing suffering.
  • βš–οΈ The script suggests that while consequentialism is intuitive, it may conflict with deeply held moral intuitions, such as the wrongness of rape or murder, which could lead to its rejection.

Q & A

  • What are the three main ethical theories discussed in the script?

    -The three main ethical theories discussed in the script are consequentialism, deontological ethics (also called conscient ethics), and virtue ethics.

  • What is consequentialism and how does it relate to utilitarianism?

    -Consequentialism is an ethical theory where the morality of an action is determined by its consequences. Utilitarianism is a popular version of consequentialism, focusing on maximizing happiness or minimizing suffering as the measure of good consequences.

  • Who are the early proponents of utilitarianism mentioned in the script?

    -The early proponents of utilitarianism mentioned in the script are Jeremy Bentham and John Stuart Mill.

  • What is the principle of utility as described in the script?

    -The principle of utility requires that in all circumstances, a person chooses the available action that maximizes happiness. It is the core principle of utilitarianism.

  • What are the three principles of hedonistic act utilitarianism?

    -The three principles of hedonistic act utilitarianism are: 1) All actions are to be judged right or wrong solely by their consequences, 2) The amount of happiness created or unhappiness avoided is the only factor in assessing consequences, and 3) Every person's happiness counts exactly the same.

  • What is the difference between act utilitarianism and rule utilitarianism?

    -Act utilitarianism evaluates the morality of an action based on its specific consequences, while rule utilitarianism evaluates actions based on whether they follow rules that generally produce the best outcomes.

  • How does the script suggest evaluating moral theories?

    -The script suggests evaluating moral theories by comparing them against our firm moral intuitions and using a process called reflective equilibrium, which involves balancing our intuitions with the implications of the theory.

  • What is reflective equilibrium and how does it relate to moral theory evaluation?

    -Reflective equilibrium is a process where one compares their firmly held moral views with the implications of moral theories, adjusting their intuitions or rejecting theories that conflict with their strongly held moral beliefs.

  • What are some potential arguments against consequentialism or act utilitarianism as hinted in the script?

    -The script hints at potential arguments against consequentialism or act utilitarianism by suggesting that it may conflict with strongly held moral intuitions, such as the wrongness of rape, murder, or child molestation.

  • What is the significance of the term 'reductio ad absurdum' in the context of evaluating moral theories?

    -The term 'reductio ad absurdum' refers to a form of argument where one shows a theory to be false by demonstrating that it leads to an absurd or unacceptable conclusion, such as justifying actions that are widely considered morally wrong.

  • Why might someone be interested in arguments against utilitarianism despite finding it intuitive?

    -Someone might be interested in arguments against utilitarianism to critically examine its weaknesses and ensure that it aligns with all moral intuitions, even if it seems intuitively appealing.

Outlines

00:00

πŸ” Introduction to Normative Ethics and Consequentialism

This paragraph introduces the topic of normative ethical theory, specifically consequentialism, and distinguishes it from discussions about the foundations of morality. The speaker sets aside questions about the objective nature of morality or its basis in religion and culture, focusing instead on how individuals make moral decisions in daily life. Consequentialism, also known as utilitarianism, is presented as one of the major ethical theories, alongside deontological ethics and virtue ethics. The paragraph outlines the basic idea of consequentialism: the morality of an action is determined solely by its consequences. If the consequences are good, the action is morally right; if bad, it is morally wrong. The speaker also introduces the concept of different versions of consequentialism, with utilitarianism being the most popular and often used interchangeably with consequentialism. The historical figures Jeremy Bentham and John Stuart Mill are mentioned as early proponents of utilitarianism, and the principle of utility, which guides actions toward maximizing happiness, is briefly discussed.

05:00

πŸ“š Principles of Hedonistic Act Utilitarianism

The second paragraph delves into the specifics of hedonistic act utilitarianism, also known as classical utilitarianism. Three key principles are outlined: (1) the moral rightness or wrongness of actions is judged solely by their consequences, (2) the primary consideration in assessing consequences is the amount of happiness created or unhappiness avoided, and (3) every person's happiness is to be considered equally. The paragraph emphasizes the mathematical and calculative nature of utilitarianism, where actions are chosen based on their potential to maximize overall happiness. The speaker also touches on the intuitive appeal of utilitarianism, suggesting that it aligns with the common-sense notion of promoting happiness and reducing suffering. Arguments in favor of utilitarianism are briefly mentioned, including the moral obligation to improve the world and the theory's ability to withstand objections better than other ethical theories. However, the main focus is on potential arguments against utilitarianism, which are said to be explored in more detail in subsequent discussions.

10:02

πŸ€” Evaluating Consequentialism Against Moral Intuitions

The final paragraph discusses the process of evaluating moral theories, such as consequentialism, against our firmly held moral intuitions. The concept of reflective equilibrium is introduced, where one's moral intuitions are compared with the implications of a moral theory, potentially leading to adjustments in one's beliefs. The speaker emphasizes the importance of not holding all moral intuitions as equally strong, allowing for the possibility of revising some intuitions in light of a compelling moral theory. However, if a theory contradicts deeply held moral convictions, such as condoning rape or slavery, it may be rejected. The paragraph concludes by suggesting that consequentialism might lead to conclusions that conflict with our strong moral intuitions, providing reasons to potentially reject the theory. The speaker indicates that further exploration of these issues will be covered in the next video.

Mindmap

Keywords

πŸ’‘Normative ethical theory

Normative ethical theory refers to a branch of ethical philosophy that seeks to understand how we ought to act, or how we can determine what is morally right or wrong. In the video, the discussion shifts from the meta-ethical question of whether there is an objective morality to the normative question of how we make moral decisions in everyday life.

πŸ’‘Consequentialism

Consequentialism is an ethical theory where the morality of an action is determined by its consequences. The video explains that consequentialism is one of the most popular views among philosophers and is the starting point for discussing how to live a morally right life.

πŸ’‘Utilitarianism

Utilitarianism is a specific form of consequentialism that focuses on maximizing overall happiness or pleasure. It is mentioned in the script as the most popular version of consequentialism, often used interchangeably with the term consequentialism.

πŸ’‘Deontological ethics

Deontological ethics, also known as duty ethics, is another major ethical theory that emphasizes the inherent morality or immorality of actions based on whether they adhere to a set of rules or duties, rather than their consequences.

πŸ’‘Virtue ethics

Virtue ethics is an ethical theory that focuses on the character of the moral agent, emphasizing virtues such as courage, honesty, and wisdom. The video mentions that the speaker is a virtue ethicist, contrasting his views with his wife's consequentialism.

πŸ’‘Principle of utility

The principle of utility is central to utilitarianism and requires that a person chooses the action that maximizes happiness in any given situation. The video explains that this principle is used to determine the right action according to utilitarianism.

πŸ’‘Hedonistic act utilitarianism

Hedonistic act utilitarianism is a type of utilitarianism that judges actions based on the amount of happiness or unhappiness they create. The video discusses this as one of the types of utilitarianism, focusing on the classical principles associated with it.

πŸ’‘Act utilitarianism

Act utilitarianism is a form of consequentialism where each individual action is evaluated for its moral worth based on its consequences. The video contrasts this with rule utilitarianism, which evaluates actions based on adherence to rules that produce good outcomes.

πŸ’‘Rule utilitarianism

Rule utilitarianism is a form of consequentialism that evaluates actions based on whether they follow rules that, if generally adhered to, would maximize overall happiness. The video mentions this in the context of different types of utilitarianism.

πŸ’‘Reflective equilibrium

Reflective equilibrium is a process in moral philosophy where one reflects on their moral intuitions and the implications of moral theories to reach a coherent set of moral beliefs. The video describes how this process can lead to the acceptance or rejection of a moral theory based on its alignment with firmly held moral views.

πŸ’‘Moral intuition

Moral intuition refers to the immediate, often unconscious, judgments we make about the moral status of actions. The video discusses how moral theories can sometimes conflict with our moral intuitions, leading us to question or adjust our beliefs.

Highlights

Discussion on normative ethical theory shifts from the foundation of morality to how to make morally right decisions.

Introduction to consequentialism as a popular view on how to live a morally right life.

Consequentialism, also known as utilitarianism, is a major philosophical view that judges actions by their consequences.

Utilitarianism's popularity among philosophers and its association with consequentialism.

Jeremy Bentham and John Stuart Mill as early proponents of utilitarianism.

The principle of utility in utilitarianism requires choosing actions that maximize happiness.

Different versions of consequentialism and their approaches to determining good or bad consequences.

Hedonistic act utilitarianism as a type of utilitarianism focusing on happiness and suffering.

Three main principles of hedonistic act utilitarianism: consequences, happiness, and equal consideration of everyone's happiness.

Arguments for utilitarianism based on moral obligation to improve the world and its defense against objections.

Utilitarianism's claim that it is the only possible option in light of failures of other ethical theories.

The process of reflective equilibrium in evaluating moral theories against firmly held moral views.

Potential conflicts between utilitarianism and strongly held moral intuitions, such as the permissibility of rape or murder.

The importance of considering the implications of consequentialism and how it may challenge our moral intuitions.

Upcoming discussion on arguments against utilitarianism and its potential to run afoul of our moral intuitions.

Transcripts

play00:00

so now we are talking about normative

play00:02

ethical theory so the what we were

play00:03

talking about before was is there a

play00:06

objective morality is there universal

play00:08

morality or is it just relative to

play00:09

opinions or cultures or things like that

play00:12

is god the foundation of morality but

play00:13

now we're leaving aside those questions

play00:16

about what's the foundation of morality

play00:18

and now we're saying okay so in our

play00:20

everyday lives as we go through and we

play00:22

have to make decisions how do we make

play00:25

those decisions and live a way that's

play00:27

morally right or morally wrong right and

play00:29

so now we're looking at those and i like

play00:32

to think of them as kind of like

play00:33

functions right where you say here's an

play00:36

action and i put it in if you know

play00:37

mathematical functions you fill in the

play00:39

little x and then you get an answer

play00:41

there so how do we live a morally right

play00:43

life one of the more popular views is

play00:46

what's called consequentialism we're

play00:47

going to cover several different

play00:49

views in the class we'll cover about

play00:51

five there's three main theories though

play00:54

that would be consequentialism

play00:56

deontological ethics also called

play00:58

conscient ethics and virtue ethics and

play01:00

so those are the big three we'll say and

play01:02

we're starting with consequentialism

play01:05

which you'll also hear referred to as

play01:07

utilitarianism and it's one of the most

play01:09

widely held views among philosophers

play01:13

virtue ethics has a lot of followers and

play01:15

deontological maybe even a little more

play01:16

than consequentialist but they're all

play01:19

major views and my wife who is

play01:21

definitely not sleeping on my office

play01:23

floor next to me definitely not is a

play01:26

consequentialist and so we always have

play01:28

these uh discussions at home a lot

play01:30

because i'm a virtue ethicist and she

play01:32

always leans toward consequentialism in

play01:34

things when we talk about and so this is

play01:36

her preferred theory i like to say

play01:39

and it is very popular one in philosophy

play01:41

as well and the idea is that whether an

play01:44

act is right or wrong depends entirely

play01:47

on the consequences of the act if the

play01:49

consequences are good the act is right

play01:52

if the consequences are bad the act is

play01:54

wrong

play01:55

but then how do we determine you know

play01:57

whether a consequence is good or bad it

play02:00

sounds i mean that makes sense

play02:02

in the beginning right you have this

play02:04

idea that if the consequences of your

play02:06

actions if you do something and then a

play02:09

lot of this other good stuff happens or

play02:11

more good comes about then that looks

play02:13

sounds pretty good and if we do

play02:15

something and more bad comes about that

play02:16

that sounds pretty bad and that makes

play02:18

good kind of intuitive sense to us but

play02:21

then how are we to determine whether the

play02:22

consequence is good or bad

play02:25

and different versions of

play02:27

consequentialism have different answers

play02:29

the most popular

play02:32

version of consequentialism

play02:34

is called utilitarianism and in fact um

play02:38

utilitarianism is so popular uh in

play02:40

consequentialism that you'll often hear

play02:42

those use interchangeably people will

play02:45

talk about being a utilitarian when

play02:46

they're talking about consequentialism

play02:48

and so and you'll hear me do that a lot

play02:50

too uh they just call consequentialism

play02:53

um utilitarianism and so you'll because

play02:56

that's what most most consequentialists

play02:58

are uh utilitarian and so we're going to

play03:01

focus mainly on a couple different types

play03:04

of utilitarianism the early proponents

play03:07

of

play03:08

utilitarianism were jeremy bentham and

play03:10

jon stewart mill jeremy bentham also

play03:12

famous for kind of

play03:14

developing the prison systems that we

play03:16

have today so not a great thing but jon

play03:19

stewart mill you might hear about him in

play03:22

different contexts in your political

play03:24

science classes and things like that as

play03:25

well

play03:26

the idea of utilitarianism is based on

play03:30

the principle of utility and this

play03:33

requires that in all circumstances this

play03:36

is what the principle of utility is it

play03:38

requires that in all circumstances

play03:40

a person chooses the available action

play03:43

that maximizes happiness so if you are

play03:47

about to do something you don't have

play03:49

every option available to you right

play03:51

usually there's only a few different

play03:52

things you can do in that situation you

play03:54

know give to the person who's poor or

play03:56

not give if you don't have any money you

play03:58

can't give

play04:00

if you can't change the laws of the

play04:03

world that have made the person

play04:05

in the situation they are there's only

play04:07

certain things you can do and the

play04:08

consequentialist says the thing the

play04:10

action that's available to you according

play04:12

to the principle of utility whichever

play04:14

action out of all the actions available

play04:16

to you the one that brings about the

play04:19

most happiness

play04:21

is the one that you should do and this

play04:22

is a type of utilitarianism called

play04:25

hedonistic act utilitarianism which

play04:27

we'll talk about more it was a radical

play04:29

idea at the time it's not so much now

play04:32

most people now agree that you should

play04:34

oppose suffering and promote happiness

play04:37

um

play04:38

that just seems kind of natural to think

play04:41

that in morality we should do the things

play04:44

that reduces suffering and makes

play04:46

happiness or good good well-being more

play04:50

prevalent

play04:53

there are different types of

play04:54

utilitarianism there's act

play04:57

utilitarianism and rule utilitarianism

play05:00

there's hidden hedonistic utilitarianism

play05:02

and preference

play05:04

utilitarianism our focus is going to be

play05:06

on act and rule

play05:09

utilitarianism we're not hedonistic act

play05:11

and rule utilitarianism we're not going

play05:13

to talk too much about preference

play05:14

utilitarianism although there's some

play05:16

things that you can

play05:18

read in the module about that as well

play05:20

so let me talk to you about the three

play05:22

principles of hedonistic act

play05:24

utilitarianism this is called classical

play05:26

utilitarianism

play05:27

this is the type that you'll probably

play05:29

most identify with and

play05:31

is the easiest to follow

play05:33

there are three principles of this the

play05:35

first principle is that all actions are

play05:37

to be judged right and wrong

play05:39

solely by virtue of the consequences

play05:42

nothing else matters only the

play05:44

consequences matter when we're talking

play05:46

about whether or not you should do an

play05:47

action or a person should do an action

play05:49

or a government should do an action we

play05:51

look at the consequences and the

play05:53

consequences alone determine whether or

play05:56

not we should do it we don't consider

play05:58

anything else just the consequences of

play06:00

the actions the second principle is that

play06:02

in assessing the consequences the only

play06:05

thing that matters is the amount of

play06:07

happiness

play06:09

that is created or unhappiness that is

play06:12

avoided

play06:13

everything else is irrelevant so if you

play06:16

reduce suffering

play06:18

and increase happiness whatever action

play06:21

is available to you that will either

play06:22

increase the happiness or reduce the

play06:24

most suffering that is the right thing

play06:27

so that's the second principle the third

play06:29

principle is that every person's

play06:31

happiness counts exactly the same so you

play06:33

can't count your happiness more than

play06:35

anybody else's so there are other

play06:37

ethical theories out there you know

play06:38

called egoism where you only concern

play06:41

yourself with your happiness that's not

play06:43

what this theory is you do consider your

play06:46

happiness but it counts for just the

play06:47

same as anybody else's happiness so when

play06:50

you do the math and this is a very mathy

play06:52

type of

play06:54

normative theory you do the calculations

play06:56

and you count yourself and your own

play06:58

happiness as well but you have to count

play07:00

it just as one and then

play07:02

add up all the happiness that

play07:04

is brought to others or all the

play07:07

suffering that is reduced for yourself

play07:09

and for others so

play07:10

every person counts equally that's

play07:13

really important for this theory

play07:15

now there are some arguments for this in

play07:18

favor of this uh there's kind of a

play07:21

presumption that there's a moral

play07:23

obligation to make the world a better

play07:24

place right that sounds like what

play07:26

morality is uh you should do things that

play07:29

make the world a better place uh that's

play07:32

kind of our intuition on that and that

play07:34

seems uncontroversial and that's exactly

play07:36

what this theory says you're supposed to

play07:38

do

play07:39

um

play07:40

and other people say well look

play07:41

consequentialism can be defended against

play07:44

uh

play07:45

other objections and all the other main

play07:47

theories seem to fail so

play07:48

consequentialism is

play07:50

our utilitarianism is the only possible

play07:53

option so those are the ways that people

play07:54

argue for i'm more interested in giving

play07:57

arguments against it right now not

play07:59

because i want to defeat it or anything

play08:00

like that uh but just because i think um

play08:03

as we're giving these theories this one

play08:06

is very intuitive and i think that you

play08:09

don't need a lot of motivation for

play08:11

believing this theory is true but then

play08:13

there are some real problems with it and

play08:14

i want to talk about some of those now

play08:17

so let me give you a couple of arguments

play08:18

against

play08:19

uh utilitarianism or act

play08:21

consequentialism

play08:23

remember that

play08:24

we evaluate um this against our firm the

play08:28

way that we're evaluating our theories

play08:30

is we're looking at our firm moral

play08:32

judgment so let me back up a little bit

play08:35

there's this process called reflective

play08:37

equilibrium and what we do in reflective

play08:40

equilibrium is we look at what our

play08:43

firmly held moral views are before we

play08:46

look at the theories themselves so for

play08:49

instance

play08:50

rape is wrong right we're just going to

play08:52

say that is a non-negotiable

play08:55

murder is wrong i'm not talking about

play08:57

killing a self-defense murder is defined

play08:59

as taking the life of an innocent person

play09:03

child molestation we can give a whole

play09:04

list of things that are non-negotiable

play09:06

right and so we think of those and we

play09:09

and we hold those views just out of our

play09:11

moral intuitions um and so then we're

play09:14

going to look at what a moral theory

play09:16

says and sometimes we change our moral

play09:19

intuitions right we might be naturally

play09:22

um

play09:22

racist or something and we find out

play09:25

through the moral theory that it's wrong

play09:27

i know that's a stupid example that's

play09:28

another clear you know example of what

play09:31

something is wrong but we sometimes our

play09:33

our moral intuitions are changed by the

play09:36

moral theory but sometimes we reject a

play09:39

moral theory because of what it does

play09:43

because it it conflicts with our

play09:45

strongly held moral intuitions now we

play09:47

can't hold all of our moral intuitions

play09:50

strongly these are just the things off

play09:51

the top of our heads we have to you know

play09:53

leave rooms for things like we're gonna

play09:55

be discussing like abortion in this

play09:57

class and we'll be discussing selling

play09:59

human organs and we'll be discussing

play10:01

access to health care and things like

play10:03

that those kinds of things we want to

play10:05

see what the moral theories say and we

play10:08

adjust our intuitions about what's right

play10:11

and wrong in those ideas based on the

play10:12

moral theories but sometimes we just

play10:14

would we'll reject a moral theory if it

play10:16

runs afoul of our strongly held moral

play10:19

intuitions

play10:20

we've talked a little bit before about a

play10:22

reductio ad absurdum argument so if we

play10:25

say that okay this theory a consequence

play10:28

of this theory is that it is okay to

play10:31

rape then we go no that theory is wrong

play10:33

then we don't know anything else about

play10:35

that theory but we know that theory is

play10:37

wrong because it says it's okay to write

play10:39

because that's a strongly held moral

play10:40

intuition so if a theory comes and sells

play10:43

to something like slavery is okay our

play10:45

murder is right or rape is right or

play10:47

molesting a child is right or something

play10:48

like that then we know that there's a

play10:50

problem with the theory

play10:52

right but sometimes we'll say well i

play10:54

think you know

play10:56

maybe the death penalty is okay but then

play10:58

we look at a moral theory and we say

play11:00

well if that moral theory is right then

play11:02

the death penalty is wrong and if we

play11:04

have more reason to believe the moral

play11:05

theory so that's what we're doing we're

play11:06

doing this balancing act that's why it's

play11:08

reflective equilibrium wayne and things

play11:11

we're so we're looking at our strongly

play11:12

held moral intuitions we're looking at

play11:13

what it says and that's what we're going

play11:15

to do when we evaluate consequentialism

play11:18

especially because it seems like

play11:20

sometimes the implications of

play11:21

consequentialism is something that we

play11:23

think is obviously wrong

play11:25

and so that gives us reason to reject uh

play11:28

consequentialism so i thought i was

play11:30

going to get deeper into that but

play11:32

i'm just going to save the actual ways

play11:34

so i'm going to give you a few reasons

play11:36

to say that

play11:38

to show you how maybe consequentialism

play11:40

or act utilitarianism will run afoul of

play11:43

our strongly held moral intuitions and

play11:45

that would give you reason to reject the

play11:46

theory and i'll do that in the next

play11:48

video

Rate This
β˜…
β˜…
β˜…
β˜…
β˜…

5.0 / 5 (0 votes)

Related Tags
Ethical TheoryConsequentialismDeontologyVirtue EthicsUtilitarianismMoral PhilosophyJeremy BenthamJohn Stuart MillPrinciple of UtilityReflective Equilibrium