The Euthyphro Dilemma: Religion and Morality (Divine Command Theory)

teachphilosophy
3 Nov 201517:41

Summary

TLDRThis script explores the Euthyphro dilemma, challenging the divine command theory of morality. It presents two horns: morality is either arbitrary, with God's commands determining goodness, or God is not the source of morality and is subject to an external moral law. The third option, that God is goodness itself, is also critiqued as collapsing into the first two. The discussion prompts a deeper examination of the relationship between morality and religion, questioning whether morality can be based solely on God's commands.

Takeaways

  • 📜 The Euthyphro dilemma explores the relationship between ethics and religion, specifically whether morality is derived from God's commands or if God's commands are moral because they align with an independent standard of goodness.
  • 🙏 Divine Command Theory posits that an act is morally good if God commands it and morally bad if God forbids it.
  • 🤔 The Euthyphro dilemma presents two horns: if God wills something because it's good, it implies a moral standard outside of God; if something is good because God wills it, morality becomes arbitrary.
  • 👶 The dilemma illustrates the problem with divine command theory by asking whether actions like drowning children for fun could become morally good if God commanded them.
  • 🧐 Intelligent theists and atheists recognize the Euthyphro dilemma as a deep philosophical problem that challenges the basis of divine command theory.
  • 🖼️ The script uses three pictures to visually represent the dilemma's options and the implications of each.
  • 🔄 The first option (God wills it because it's good) is problematic because it suggests there's a standard of goodness independent of God, making God a 'middleman' rather than the source of morality.
  • 🔄 The second option (it's good because God wills it) is criticized for making morality arbitrary and dependent solely on God's will, which could change at any time.
  • 🔄 The third option (God is goodness) is considered but collapses into the first two options when considering whether God's essence was chosen or inherent.
  • 📚 The Euthyphro dilemma is not an argument against God's existence but a challenge to the idea that morality can be based solely on God's commands.
  • 💭 The script encourages deep reflection on the dilemma and suggests that even divine command theorists often rely on reasons for morality that are independent of God's commands.

Q & A

  • What is Divine Command Theory?

    -Divine Command Theory is the belief that things are good because God commands them, and things are bad because God forbids them. In this view, morality is determined by God's will.

  • What is the Euthyphro Dilemma as presented in the script?

    -The Euthyphro Dilemma asks whether something is good because God wills it, or if God wills it because it is good. This presents a challenge to Divine Command Theory by questioning whether morality is arbitrary or if there is a standard of goodness independent of God.

  • What is the first problem with the view that morality is based solely on God's commands?

    -The first problem is that it makes morality arbitrary. If morality is determined solely by God's will, then God could command anything, even morally heinous acts like killing children, and it would be considered good.

  • How does Divine Command Theory lead to moral arbitrariness?

    -If morality is based solely on what God commands, then any act, no matter how cruel or unjust, could be deemed good if God wills it. This makes morality subject to change and potentially arbitrary.

  • What is the second option of the Euthyphro Dilemma?

    -The second option is that God commands something because it is good. However, this implies that goodness exists independently of God, which challenges the idea of God as the ultimate source of morality.

  • Why is the second option problematic for monotheists?

    -The second option suggests that there is an independent standard of goodness outside of God, which contradicts the belief that God is the omnipotent source of all goodness. It turns God into a 'middleman' rather than the creator of moral law.

  • What is the third option some propose to resolve the Euthyphro Dilemma?

    -Some propose that God is goodness itself, and morality flows from God's essence rather than being arbitrary or based on an independent standard. This view attempts to reconcile the dilemma by suggesting that God's essence is inherently good.

  • How does the third option still face issues related to the Euthyphro Dilemma?

    -The third option faces the issue of whether God chose His essence. If God chose His essence, then He could have chosen an essence that allows for morally wrong acts. If God did not choose His essence, then there is something independent of God that determines His essence, which brings back the original dilemma.

  • What is the challenge to Divine Command Theory presented by examples like Abraham and modern-day religious extremists?

    -The challenge is that if morality is solely based on God's commands, there is no way to know whether God might command morally heinous acts, as in the story of Abraham being commanded to sacrifice his son. This raises concerns about the reliability of basing morality on divine commands alone.

  • What does the script suggest is the relationship between reason, empathy, and morality in opposition to Divine Command Theory?

    -The script suggests that even intelligent theists believe God gave humans reason and empathy to discover what is morally right and wrong. Morality should be based on these factors to promote human flourishing, rather than being solely reliant on God's commands.

Outlines

00:00

📜 Introduction to Divine Command Theory and the Euthyphro Dilemma

This paragraph introduces the concept of Divine Command Theory, which posits that something is good because God commands it, and bad because God forbids it. It discusses the Euthyphro Dilemma, a philosophical problem that arises from this theory. The dilemma is presented as a choice between two options: either God commands something because it is good, or something is good because God commands it. The paragraph emphasizes the depth of the problem, suggesting that even if everyone agreed on God's existence and commands, the dilemma would persist. It also introduces the Socratic dialogue 'Euthyphro' as a key text for exploring this issue.

05:01

🔍 The Euthyphro Dilemma: Exploring the Two Options

The second paragraph delves into the Euthyphro Dilemma, examining the implications of the second option—that something is good because God wills it. It points out that this view can make morality arbitrary, as God's commands could change and thus alter what is considered morally good or bad. The paragraph uses illustrations to help understand the dilemma and suggests that even if God's will were known, the theory would still face problems. It also touches on the idea that many people who claim to be divine command theorists actually base their morality on other principles, such as the inherent wrongness of killing innocent life.

10:03

🤔 The First Option of the Euthyphro Dilemma: God Commands Because It's Good

This paragraph explores the first option of the Euthyphro Dilemma, which suggests that God commands something because it is inherently good. It argues that this view implies a standard of goodness that exists independently of God, which contradicts the belief that God is the source of all goodness. The paragraph uses the analogy of good parenting to illustrate how God might be seen as a recognizer rather than a creator of goodness. It also introduces a third option, which is not fully developed but suggests that God is goodness itself, and that goodness naturally flows from God's essence.

15:03

🧐 The Complexity of the Third Option and Philosophical Implications

The fourth paragraph continues the discussion of the third option, suggesting that it may collapse into the first two options of the Euthyphro Dilemma. It raises the question of whether God's essence is chosen or inherent, which echoes the original dilemma. The paragraph also reflects on the philosophical implications of the Euthyphro Dilemma, suggesting that it challenges the idea that morality can be based solely on divine commands. It encourages further exploration of the relationship between morality and religion and provides questions for deeper understanding.

Mindmap

Keywords

💡Divine Command Theory

Divine Command Theory is a philosophical and ethical concept that suggests an action is morally right because a god commands it, and morally wrong if the god forbids it. This theory is central to the video's exploration of the relationship between ethics and religion. The video uses examples such as 'homosexuality, slavery, and genocide' to illustrate how this theory might be applied, arguing that these things are wrong because 'God forbids them.'

💡Euthyphro Dilemma

The Euthyphro Dilemma, derived from Plato's dialogue 'Euthyphro,' is a philosophical question that challenges the Divine Command Theory by asking whether a thing is good because God loves it, or does God love it because it is good. This dilemma is the crux of the video's argument, presenting a problem that even if everyone agreed on God's existence and commands, the question of morality's basis would remain.

💡Morality

Morality, in the context of the video, refers to a set of principles or rules that distinguish between right and wrong or good and bad behavior. The video explores whether morality is derived from divine commands or if it exists independently. It discusses how morality might be seen as arbitrary if it's solely based on God's commands.

💡Aristotelian

Aristotelian refers to the philosophical traditions and ideas stemming from the ancient Greek philosopher Aristotle. While not explicitly mentioned, the video's discussion of 'flourishing in life' echoes Aristotelian concepts of eudaimonia, or human flourishing, which is a key component in Aristotle's ethical theory.

💡Arbitrary

Arbitrary, in the video, is used to describe a situation where something is decided or done capriciously or by chance, without a discernible pattern or reason. The video argues that if morality is based solely on divine command, then it becomes arbitrary because God could command anything to be good, and it would be so.

💡Omnipotent

Omnipotent refers to the concept of having unlimited power or being able to do anything. The video discusses the implications of God's omnipotence in relation to the Divine Command Theory, questioning whether God's nature (essence) is something He chose or something that chose Him.

💡Epistemological Source

Epistemological Source pertains to the origin of knowledge or understanding. The video suggests that while God or parents might be the source from which we learn about morality, they are not necessarily the source that makes actions morally right or wrong.

💡Metaphysical Source

Metaphysical Source refers to the fundamental nature or essence of something. The video contrasts the epistemological source with the metaphysical source, arguing that while we might learn about morality from God, the goodness or badness of actions has a metaphysical basis that is independent of God's commands.

💡Goodness

Goodness, in the video, is used to describe the quality of being good or morally right. It is discussed in the context of whether goodness is inherent to an act or if it is bestowed upon an act by God's command, which is central to the Euthyphro Dilemma.

💡Cultural Relativism

Cultural Relativism is the idea that moral or ethical principles are determined by one's own culture and are not universal. The video briefly touches on this by suggesting that if morality is based on what a culture wills, similar issues to Divine Command Theory would arise.

💡Empathy

Empathy is the ability to understand and share the feelings of others. The video mentions empathy as a human emotion that might guide moral decisions, independent of divine commands, suggesting that morality is not solely based on what God wills but also on human emotions and understanding.

Highlights

Exploring the relationship between ethics and religion.

Introduction to divine command theory.

The Euthyphro dilemma presented by Plato.

Socrates' question to Euthyphro about the nature of piety.

The dilemma of whether God wills something because it's good or if it's good because God wills it.

Critique of divine command theory making morality arbitrary.

The problem of knowing God's will and its implications for morality.

The argument that morality is not solely based on God's commands.

The suggestion that God commands something because it's good, not the other way around.

The issue of God being a 'middleman' in the first option of the dilemma.

The proposal of a third option where God is goodness itself.

The potential collapse of the third option into the first two horns of the dilemma.

The question of whether people discover the mind of God when they discover morality.

The Euthyphro dilemma as a challenge to divine command theory rather than an argument against God's existence.

The application of the Euthyphro dilemma in understanding the relationship between morality and religion.

The importance of the Euthyphro dilemma in philosophical discussions about morality and religion.

The suggestion that even divine command theorists often rely on God-independent reasons for morality.

Transcripts

play00:00

so in this week's ethical readings

play00:03

you're exploring the relationship

play00:05

between ethics and religion so as you

play00:08

explore the relationship between

play00:09

religion and morality you'll find that

play00:11

some people believe things are good

play00:12

because God commands them and some

play00:15

things are bad because god forbids them

play00:16

this is called divine command theory so

play00:19

for example if you argue that

play00:20

homosexuality slavery and genocide are

play00:22

wrong because god forbids them then

play00:25

you're using divine command theory but

play00:27

intelligent theists and atheists are

play00:29

aware that there is a deep problem with

play00:31

basing your morality and what God

play00:32

commands and it's not simply that people

play00:34

disagree about God's existence or what

play00:36

God commands there's a deeper problem

play00:38

that is even if everyone agreed that God

play00:40

exists and agreed on what God commands

play00:42

this problem would remain and this

play00:45

problem is called the Euthyphro dilemma

play00:46

a dilemma is when there's two choices

play00:49

and neither of the two choices is good

play00:51

so what is the Euthyphro dilemma

play00:53

well Plato wrote a dialogue called the

play00:55

Euthyphro and you'll be reading this

play00:58

dialogue and answering questions about

play00:59

it at the end of this lesson in the

play01:01

dialogue Socrates is talking to a

play01:03

religious man named Euthyphro now at one

play01:06

point and this is the most important

play01:08

point in the dialogue Socrates asked

play01:09

Euthyphro whether the gods loved pious

play01:11

acts because their pious or if it's

play01:14

pious because it's loved by the gods

play01:16

so the question can be phrased for the

play01:18

modern monotheists in the following way

play01:20

does God will it because it's good or is

play01:24

it good because God wills it this is a

play01:28

deep question and I recommend that you

play01:29

think carefully about it before giving

play01:31

an answer now Euthyphro could not

play01:34

adequately answer this question and many

play01:36

theists have struggled with it ever

play01:37

since so let's look at the two options

play01:40

of the dilemma and as we proceed I have

play01:42

three lovely pictures I drew to help you

play01:44

understand this dilemma so let's start

play01:46

with the second option the second option

play01:48

was it is good because God wills it and

play01:51

it has a few problems now one obvious

play01:53

problem again is knowing God's will

play01:55

people disagree about what God's will

play01:56

which is one reason why there's so many

play01:58

religions but this is a superficial

play01:59

problem there's a deeper problem that

play02:02

exists even when we assume God exists

play02:04

and we agree on what God wills and

play02:05

commands now before getting into these

play02:08

deeper problems notice again that the

play02:09

second option is divine command theory

play02:11

which is the position that

play02:13

determines morality that is morally good

play02:15

acts are those that God commands a

play02:16

morally bad X are those that come from

play02:18

bids right so again if you think

play02:20

homosexuality is wrong simply because

play02:22

god forbids it then your divine command

play02:24

theorists right it doesn't matter if

play02:26

homosexuality is natural or unnatural or

play02:28

whether it promotes happiness all that

play02:30

matters to the divine command theorists

play02:32

in the end is that god forbids it or

play02:34

allows it so let's examine this problem

play02:36

with arguing that morality is nothing

play02:38

but what God commands the problems with

play02:40

the second horn dilemma now the first

play02:43

problem with basing morality solely on

play02:45

what God commands is that it seems to

play02:47

make morality arbitrary okay since God

play02:50

could command anything to be good and it

play02:52

would suddenly be good for example let's

play02:54

say divine command theory is correct and

play02:56

it's round around kids for fun because

play02:58

god forbids it

play02:59

now if the morally good act is simply

play03:01

what God commands then God could change

play03:02

his mind tomorrow and command that I

play03:04

drowned my kids in a bathtub and that

play03:06

act would suddenly become good it

play03:08

doesn't matter if I think killing

play03:10

children is usually wrong because it

play03:12

violates rights or doesn't promote

play03:13

happiness or simply goes against the

play03:15

empathy I have for kids all of these

play03:17

reasons and Maury emotions are

play03:18

irrelevant if I'm a divine command

play03:20

theorists in this case so the first and

play03:23

major problem with this second option

play03:25

it's good because God commands it is it

play03:27

makes morality arbitrary it makes

play03:29

morality like an arbitrary matter of

play03:31

taste it's good simply because God likes

play03:33

it and God could like anything at any

play03:34

time but again I just don't see how God

play03:37

commanding and the drowning of kids for

play03:39

fun would suddenly make it good I don't

play03:41

see how things are good because God

play03:42

commands or wills them now a divine

play03:44

command theorist may object and say well

play03:46

God would never command you to torture

play03:49

kill or rape children for fun but this

play03:51

response misses the point

play03:53

if divine command theory is correct the

play03:55

morality is simply based on what God

play03:56

come in so how can anyone possibly know

play03:58

God would not command these heinous acts

play04:00

to know that the person would have to

play04:03

appeal to something other than God's

play04:04

command right and so they're not really

play04:06

divine command theorists indeed there

play04:09

was recently a lady in Houston who

play04:10

believed God told her to drown her kids

play04:12

in the bathtub also God told Abraham to

play04:15

sacrifice his son so some of the

play04:16

Crusaders and many terrorists believe

play04:18

God commands them into many heinous acts

play04:20

so how do you know God won't ask you to

play04:22

kill your child tomorrow as he did

play04:24

Abraham the bottom line is that

play04:26

on command theory the second option the

play04:27

dilemma makes morality arbitrary heinous

play04:31

acts like drowning children for fun

play04:32

would suddenly become obligatory if God

play04:34

commanded them so at this point it

play04:36

should also be clear that many people

play04:39

are not really divine command theorists

play04:40

and this is because they present

play04:42

arguments like God wouldn't do that

play04:43

because it's wrong to kill an innocent

play04:45

life so their morality is really based

play04:48

on the idea that it's wrong to kill an

play04:49

innocent life not so much what somebody

play04:51

claims to be God's will now there are

play04:54

other problems with the SEC adoption you

play04:56

know it makes morality mysterious it

play04:58

gives the wrong reasons for being

play04:59

immoral you know I'll address those in

play05:01

the question suction for now I'll simply

play05:03

say that not everyone understands the

play05:05

problem here with the SEC adoption and

play05:07

this was the problem that Socrates

play05:09

outlined so long ago but Euthyphro

play05:11

atheist and many intelligent theists do

play05:13

understand the problem they understand

play05:15

that the SEC adoption implies that

play05:16

killing children for fun could be made

play05:18

moral they understand that the main

play05:20

problem with the SEC adoptions that it

play05:22

makes morality arbitrary and so they

play05:24

propose another option they propose and

play05:26

enact as good not because God commands

play05:28

it rather God commands it because it's

play05:30

good and this avoids the arbitrary

play05:32

problem because it avoids the

play05:33

implication that killing children for

play05:35

fun could become morally good tomorrow

play05:37

now however the first option God

play05:40

commands it because it's good has one

play05:42

serious problem

play05:42

it sets up a standard of goodness

play05:44

separate from God so it makes God a

play05:46

middleman this is a problem because most

play05:49

monotheists believe God is the

play05:51

omnipotent source of all goodness if God

play05:53

merely recognizes good and then informs

play05:55

us humans it follows that God is not an

play05:58

omnipotent God is not the source of all

play05:59

goodness but merely informs us about

play06:01

some independent standard of good like a

play06:04

middle man or a good parent and you can

play06:06

see this illustrated in number one so

play06:09

let's use an example imagine you have

play06:10

good parents and they train needed to be

play06:12

go to bed at a reasonable time to eat

play06:14

healthy to follow the golden rule to be

play06:16

empathetic towards others and to live a

play06:17

good moral life at some point your

play06:20

reason your intellect develops and you

play06:21

understand that these things that are

play06:22

not good because your parents commanded

play06:24

them rather your parents taught you

play06:26

these things because they're good

play06:27

perhaps because they help you flourish

play06:28

in life so you realize that your parents

play06:30

and your culture are not the source of

play06:32

goodness rather their goodness

play06:34

recognizers there are goodness

play06:35

transmitters they teach you what they

play06:37

think will lead to a good life

play06:39

just as a mother a corn you know may

play06:40

teach a baby acorn to sunbathe and get

play06:42

enough water right so if you think

play06:45

something is good merely because your

play06:46

parents are cultures say so then you

play06:48

still have an immature or undeveloped

play06:50

mindset your parents and culture are

play06:52

good recognizers not good creators so if

play06:55

the first option is correct then God is

play06:57

like a good parent God is a good

play06:59

recognizer not a good creator if the

play07:01

first option is correct there is a God

play07:03

independent standard of goodness you can

play07:05

see the Sun in a diagram so John author

play07:07

puts the point this way if God approves

play07:10

kindness because it's a virtue and hates

play07:12

the Nazis because they were evil then it

play07:14

seems that God discovers morality rather

play07:16

than inventing it God's no longer

play07:18

sovereign over the entire universe but

play07:21

rather is subject to moral law external

play07:23

to himself so this turns God into

play07:26

something like a good parent or middle

play07:27

man who discovers principles that lead

play07:29

to human flourishing and then transmits

play07:31

them to us to use philosophical jargon

play07:34

God and your parents may originally be

play07:36

the epistemological source of your

play07:38

morality that is how you come to know

play07:40

good from bad but they're not the

play07:41

metaphysical source they're not what

play07:43

makes something that are bad so now we

play07:45

have the two horns of the Euthyphro

play07:47

dilemma morality is either arbitrary

play07:49

meaning anything can be good or God is

play07:51

not the source of morality and God is

play07:54

subject to an external moral law so is

play07:56

there a solution well some people have

play07:59

presented a third option to the

play08:00

Euthyphro dilemma and this is the idea

play08:02

that God is goodness

play08:04

God doesn't arbitrarily will what is

play08:07

good rather goodness flows from God's

play08:09

essence he is goodness you can see this

play08:11

option than diagram under number three

play08:13

now to clarify number three notice that

play08:16

we may use reason to discover God's

play08:18

essence which is truth and goodness for

play08:20

example let's say Einsteins laws are

play08:22

true when we rationally discover such

play08:24

laws we are discovering the essence or

play08:26

the mind of God likewise when we

play08:29

discover that slavery is bad we are

play08:30

discovering the moral essence of God and

play08:33

this is not essential the third option

play08:35

but it's a nice way to think of it in

play08:36

short God doesn't arbitrarily we'll

play08:38

goodness as in picture 1 and 2 whether

play08:41

God is goodness so goodness flows

play08:43

inevitably from God's essence

play08:46

however this third option may fall into

play08:49

the same dilemma to see why consider

play08:51

this question

play08:52

does God choose God's essence does God

play08:55

choose God's essence now some people say

play08:57

God is omnipotent and so he can choose

play08:59

his essence if this is correct then God

play09:01

could choose a different essence but

play09:03

this presents the same dilemma that we

play09:05

found in youth Rafael

play09:06

did something else make God's essence or

play09:09

did God choose his essence if God chose

play09:11

his essence then he chose that to be

play09:12

good and if that is the case he could

play09:15

have chosen a different essence and in

play09:16

essence that enjoys drowning kids for

play09:18

example if God did not choose his

play09:21

essence then God is not omnipotent and

play09:23

subject to something else that made his

play09:24

essence so again if God chose his

play09:27

essence then he chose goodness option 2

play09:29

the problem with this option is God

play09:31

could have chosen any essence he could

play09:33

have chosen to light killing kids for

play09:35

fun if God did not choose as essence

play09:37

option 1 then something independent of

play09:39

God chose it in that case God's essence

play09:41

and goodness are independent of God and

play09:43

God becomes a good parent or middleman

play09:45

instead of the source of all goodness so

play09:47

in short the third option that I just

play09:49

explored seems to collapse into one of

play09:51

the first two options so there you have

play09:52

it

play09:53

this is the Euthyphro dilemma the first

play09:55

two options

play09:56

Socrates presented these first two

play09:58

options he didn't address the third so

play10:00

it's just as well since the third seems

play10:03

to collapse into the first two options

play10:04

now I agree with some other philosophers

play10:07

that your ability to deeply understand

play10:09

this dilemma is a reflection of whether

play10:11

you are capable of certain kind of

play10:12

philosophy whatever you think that

play10:15

Euthyphro is the portal into a much

play10:16

deeper exploration the relationship

play10:18

between morality and religion in the end

play10:21

it challenges the idea that morality can

play10:23

base be based solely on God's commands

play10:25

it's a challenge to divine command

play10:27

theory to deepen your understanding

play10:29

please review the following questions

play10:31

and possible answers then follow the

play10:33

link to the actual Euthyphro dilemma and

play10:35

answer the guided questions and again

play10:38

don't neglect those primary sources

play10:40

right there's so much more there that I

play10:41

haven't covered in this video so let's

play10:43

look at the questions real quick

play10:45

number one explain how the second option

play10:47

divine command theory makes morality

play10:49

arbitrary well killing kids for fun

play10:51

becomes automatically good if it's good

play10:53

or bad

play10:54

simply because God wills it there's no

play10:55

need to appeal to scientific facts to

play10:57

empathy to greatest happiness to rights

play10:59

the mere fact that God thinks in

play11:00

commands it would be good would make it

play11:02

so so that's the answer number one

play11:03

number two discuss whether the sign

play11:05

good option divine command theory

play11:07

motivates a person to do the right thing

play11:08

for the wrong reasons well it seems to

play11:12

give the wrong reasons for being moral

play11:13

so for example imagine a person chooses

play11:15

to not torture kittens because he

play11:19

believes it causes unnecessary suffering

play11:21

now a second person chooses to not

play11:24

torture kittens but only because of God

play11:26

forbids it now isn't the first person a

play11:28

more stable and moral okay look at

play11:32

number three

play11:32

explain why the second option divine

play11:34

command theory makes morality mysterious

play11:36

and this is from James Rachel's and it's

play11:38

elements of moral philosophy it makes it

play11:41

mysterious okay so the problem here is

play11:45

the idea that an act is good because

play11:47

what God wills it

play11:49

it makes morality mysterious we can

play11:51

understand how to make things but how do

play11:52

you make things good when we argue about

play11:55

moral matters like slavery most people

play11:57

argue slavery is wrong because it

play11:58

violates rights it doesn't promote the

play12:00

greatest happiness or it doesn't follow

play12:01

the Golden Rule

play12:02

but if divine command theory is correct

play12:04

none of that really matters all that

play12:05

matters is that God commands or forbids

play12:07

it so morality is no longer a matter of

play12:09

determining how to protect rights or

play12:11

promote happiness and now becomes a

play12:12

matter of knowing God's will and it may

play12:14

be completely mysterious as to why God

play12:16

will some things but not others so like

play12:18

some forms of relativism it just cuts

play12:20

off reasoning on moral issues okay

play12:23

number four explain why the first option

play12:25

God wills it because it's good is

play12:26

unsatisfactory to modern the monotheists

play12:30

well it's unsatisfactory because it

play12:32

presents an independent standard of

play12:33

goodness to God it turns God into a good

play12:36

parent or middlemen

play12:37

instead of the source of all goodness

play12:39

number five explain a three-picture is

play12:42

representing the three options well you

play12:43

can see that in the video number six

play12:46

explain or discuss the third option okay

play12:49

well it seems to me that the third

play12:50

option the idea that God is goodness and

play12:52

doesn't arbitrarily will good in bed

play12:54

that this option faces the same problems

play12:57

if we assume God is omnipotent could

play12:59

have chosen a different nature or

play13:00

essence for himself if God is not

play13:02

omnipotent then he did not choose his

play13:04

essence and so there's an independent

play13:05

standard making God's essence and hence

play13:07

is the true source of goodness so this

play13:10

third option can become quite complex

play13:12

and distinctions like God's essence and

play13:14

existence need to be made epistemology

play13:16

minutephysics

play13:17

but in the end I just think it collapses

play13:19

into

play13:19

first two options number seven

play13:22

can God be omnipotent if the third

play13:25

option is true

play13:26

well yeah but you know God's omnipotence

play13:29

doesn't adequately resolve the Euthyphro

play13:32

dilemma because the question then

play13:34

becomes did God get his essence or did

play13:36

God choose his essence that is is God's

play13:38

essence good because it's good or is

play13:40

God's essence good because God commanded

play13:43

and created his essence number eight do

play13:46

people discover the mind of God when

play13:48

they discover what is right and wrong

play13:50

well some people may think so but this

play13:52

third option doesn't really resolve the

play13:54

Euthyphro dilemma and you can see number

play13:56

seven for y let's see here number nine

play14:00

isn't this based on a misunderstanding

play14:01

of omnipotence

play14:03

well no I'm aware that omnipotence

play14:05

doesn't mean God can do the logically

play14:07

impossible like round a square or create

play14:09

a married bachelor

play14:10

however the Euthyphro dilemma doesn't

play14:12

depend on omnipotence it simply depends

play14:15

on whether an act is good because it's

play14:16

good or because God wills it so to

play14:18

illustrate we can substitute your

play14:20

culture for God so do you believe it's

play14:22

good because it's good or because your

play14:24

culture wills it the same issues arise

play14:26

without any claims to omnipotence okay

play14:30

the next question is the Euthyphro

play14:31

dilemma an argument against God's

play14:33

existence well no the u-thor dilemma

play14:36

doesn't prove or disprove God's

play14:37

existence rather it presents a challenge

play14:39

to anyone who bases morality and what

play14:41

they think God commends now it is a

play14:44

counter to one of the arguments for

play14:45

God's existence the moral argument but

play14:47

it itself doesn't say and God exists or

play14:49

doesn't exist another interesting

play14:52

question for the divine command theorist

play14:54

is why is it wrong to disobey God you

play14:58

know it might be because God knows

play14:59

better than us but if that's the case

play15:01

gods like a good parent not the source

play15:03

of all morality

play15:04

he's the epistemological source but not

play15:06

the metaphysical source right maybe it's

play15:09

because of power but then you would be

play15:11

following the principle that might makes

play15:12

right

play15:13

surely God doesn't want you to follow

play15:14

that principle right okay so let's look

play15:18

at the application of value here so when

play15:20

you explore the Euthyphro dilemma it can

play15:21

help you better understand the

play15:22

relationship at a deep level between if

play15:25

you have them your moral and religious

play15:27

beliefs

play15:28

now all the most intelligent in popular

play15:30

theists and atheists have struggled with

play15:32

this

play15:33

Descartes Luther and and some Hobbes and

play15:37

so on and now it's your turn right

play15:38

you're welcome

play15:39

now in my experience people often give

play15:42

simplistic answers at first for example

play15:45

they may argue that both horns of the

play15:46

dilemma dilemma are true but a little

play15:49

reflection should help you see why both

play15:50

options cannot be true second some will

play15:53

try to avoid the dilemma by arguing

play15:55

there's a third option you know God is

play15:56

goodness and this is more sophisticated

play15:58

and many fine distinctions can be made

play16:00

between essence and existence

play16:02

epistemology and metaphysics and so on

play16:03

but in the end this third option brings

play16:05

up the same dilemma you know why is

play16:07

God's essence determined or was it

play16:09

chosen and it's gonna collapse into

play16:11

those first two options again in the end

play16:14

the divine command theorist ultimately

play16:16

resorts to arguments that make morality

play16:18

a really mysterious matter instead of

play16:20

one in which we try to maximize the

play16:22

greatest happiness and protect a set of

play16:23

Rights that we agree on and they're

play16:25

essential for human flourishing now

play16:27

there very well may be a God but

play16:30

believing morality is nothing but God's

play16:32

commands is problematic and even

play16:35

intelligent theists agree with me here

play16:38

intelligent theists believe that God

play16:40

gave them reason and empathy discover

play16:41

right and wrong to discover the

play16:43

conditions that best promote human

play16:46

flourishing so even you know it's

play16:50

interesting that even the divine command

play16:51

theorists aren't usually divine command

play16:53

theorists because they often give God

play16:55

independent reasons for why we should

play16:57

obey God or act in moral ways all right

play17:00

so that's my take on the Euthyphro

play17:02

dilemma now you get to read the actual

play17:05

dialogue I included some questions for

play17:07

you here as you read enjoy Thanks

play17:17

you

Rate This

5.0 / 5 (0 votes)

関連タグ
EthicsReligionMoralityDivine CommandEuthyphro DilemmaPhilosophySocratesTheismAtheismMoral Philosophy
英語で要約が必要ですか?