The Famous 'Sheriff' Counterexample to Utilitarianism

Jeffrey Kaplan
21 Jan 202015:02

Summary

TLDRIn this philosophical discourse, the video explores the utilitarianism moral theory, focusing on H.J. McCloskey's counter-example involving a sheriff who must decide between executing an innocent man to prevent riots or allowing many deaths to occur. The video discusses the theory's consequentialism and aggregation principles, questioning whether the moral theory can justify such actions. Jay Smart's response to McCloskey's objection is also examined, where he defends utilitarianism by accepting the uncomfortable conclusion that framing an innocent person could be morally right in certain extreme circumstances.

Takeaways

  • 🔍 The script discusses a famous counterexample against utilitarianism introduced by philosopher H. J. McCloskey, which involves a sheriff and an innocent man.
  • 🤔 Utilitarianism is a moral theory that suggests actions should be judged based on the greatest total pleasure or the least total pain for all affected individuals.
  • 📚 The example is summarized by J. J. C. Smart, a utilitarian philosopher, who defends the theory against McCloskey's objection.
  • 👮‍♂️ The scenario involves a sheriff who can prevent riots and save hundreds of lives by framing and executing an innocent man.
  • 🤝 Utilitarianism, as a form of consequentialism, is based on the idea that the morality of an action is determined by its outcomes.
  • 🧩 The counterexample challenges the utilitarian principle of aggregation, which posits that the goodness of a situation is the sum of individual goods.
  • 🚫 McCloskey argues that utilitarianism's disregard for the distribution of pleasure and pain leads to morally repugnant outcomes, such as punishing the innocent.
  • 🔄 Smart's initial response to the counterexample suggests that the risk of being discovered framing an innocent person could outweigh the benefits.
  • 🔄 McCloskey's rejoinder involves tweaking the scenario to ensure the sheriff will not be discovered, thus maintaining the counterexample's challenge to utilitarianism.
  • 💡 Smart ultimately defends utilitarianism by accepting the uncomfortable conclusion that, in certain extreme cases, framing an innocent person might be the morally correct utilitarian action.

Q & A

  • What is the main argument against utilitarianism presented in the script?

    -The main argument against utilitarianism presented in the script is the Sheriff's Dilemma, introduced by H. J. McCloskey. It challenges utilitarianism by suggesting that in certain situations, such as preventing riots by executing an innocent man, utilitarianism may require actions that are morally repugnant.

  • What is utilitarianism according to the script?

    -Utilitarianism, as described in the script, is a moral theory that posits we are morally required to perform the action that will produce the greatest total amount of pleasure over pain for all involved.

  • What is the role of aggregation in utilitarianism?

    -Aggregation in utilitarianism refers to the theory that the goodness of an outcome is determined by the total or sum of how good the situation is for individual people, without considering the distribution of pleasure and pain among them.

  • What does the term 'hedonism' mean in the context of utilitarianism?

    -Hedonism, within the context of utilitarianism, is the theory that a situation is good for an individual to the extent that it maximizes their pleasure and minimizes their pain.

  • What is a counterexample in moral philosophy as discussed in the script?

    -A counterexample in moral philosophy, as discussed in the script, is a specific instance that goes against a general claim or moral theory, used to challenge the validity of that theory by demonstrating a situation where the theory's conclusion is morally unacceptable.

  • What is the Sheriff's Dilemma and how does it challenge utilitarianism?

    -The Sheriff's Dilemma is a hypothetical scenario where a sheriff must decide whether to frame and execute an innocent person to prevent riots that would kill hundreds. It challenges utilitarianism by creating a situation where the theory suggests that the morally right action is to sacrifice one innocent person for the greater good, which goes against common moral intuitions.

  • How does J.J.C. Smart respond to McCloskey's objection in the script?

    -J.J.C. Smart, a utilitarian philosopher, responds to McCloskey's objection by arguing that in the scenario presented, utilitarianism indeed suggests that the sheriff should frame the innocent person to prevent the greater harm of hundreds of deaths. Smart defends this conclusion by emphasizing the severity of the riots and the greater number of innocent lives that would be lost.

  • What does 'biting the bullet' mean in the context of the script?

    -In the context of the script, 'biting the bullet' refers to J.J.C. Smart's acceptance of the uncomfortable conclusion that, according to utilitarianism, framing an innocent person is the morally right action in the Sheriff's Dilemma scenario, despite the moral discomfort it causes.

  • Why does the script suggest that the problem with the Sheriff's Dilemma is fundamentally with the aggregation aspect of utilitarianism?

    -The script suggests that the problem with the Sheriff's Dilemma is fundamentally with the aggregation aspect of utilitarianism because aggregation focuses solely on the total sum of pleasure and pain without considering the distribution or who specifically experiences these outcomes, which leads to morally contentious conclusions.

  • What is the significance of the Sheriff's Dilemma in the broader discussion of moral philosophy?

    -The significance of the Sheriff's Dilemma in moral philosophy is that it highlights the potential conflict between utilitarianism's focus on overall outcomes and our intuitive moral judgments about individual rights and justice, prompting a deeper examination of the theory's adequacy in addressing complex moral dilemmas.

Outlines

00:00

🔍 McCluskey's Critique of Utilitarianism

The paragraph introduces H. J. McCloskey's critique of utilitarianism, which is a consequentialist moral theory advocating for actions that maximize pleasure and minimize pain. McCloskey presents a counterexample involving a sheriff who must decide whether to frame an innocent man to prevent riots that would result in many deaths. This example challenges the utilitarian principle of aggregation, which focuses on the total sum of pleasure and pain without considering distribution. The paragraph sets the stage for discussing the philosophical debate between utilitarianism and its critics.

05:01

🚔 The Sheriff's Dilemma and Utilitarianism's Challenge

This paragraph delves into the hypothetical scenario of a sheriff who can prevent a riot that would lead to hundreds of deaths by executing an innocent man. It highlights the utilitarian perspective that the sheriff is morally required to frame the innocent to achieve the best outcome in terms of overall pleasure and pain. The paragraph emphasizes the moral conflict this scenario presents, as it goes against the intuition that framing an innocent person is inherently wrong. It also points out that the crux of the issue lies in the utilitarian principle of aggregation, which is indifferent to the distribution of consequences among individuals.

10:04

🤔 Smart's Defense of Utilitarianism

The final paragraph discusses J.J.C. Smart's response to McCloskey's critique. Smart, a utilitarian philosopher, acknowledges the dilemma but argues that utilitarianism might still lead to the conclusion that the sheriff should not frame the innocent due to the risk of undermining public trust in the justice system. However, he concedes that if the sheriff is confident in not being caught, then utilitarianism would support framing the innocent to prevent the greater harm of the riots. Smart ultimately defends the utilitarian conclusion, even though it is uncomfortable, by emphasizing the severity of the riots and the greater number of innocent lives that would be lost. He 'bites the bullet' by accepting the utilitarian stance that, in this extreme scenario, framing the innocent is morally right.

Mindmap

Keywords

💡Utilitarianism

Utilitarianism is a moral theory that posits the moral worth of an action is determined by its outcome, specifically the extent to which it maximizes overall happiness or pleasure. In the video, this theory is central as it is the subject of critique through McCloskey's Sheriff example. The example challenges utilitarianism by suggesting that it may require morally repugnant actions, such as framing an innocent person, for the greater good.

💡Consequentialism

Consequentialism is a broader ethical theory that asserts the morality of an action is determined by its consequences. It is mentioned in the video as the overarching category to which utilitarianism belongs. According to consequentialism, actions are to be evaluated based on the goodness of their outcomes, which ties directly into the discussion of the Sheriff example and its implications for utilitarianism.

💡Aggregation

Aggregation, in the context of the video, refers to the process of summing up the individual benefits and harms to determine the overall goodness of a situation. It is a key component of utilitarianism and is challenged by McCloskey's example, which suggests that simply adding up the total pleasure or pain may not account for the distribution of consequences among individuals.

💡Hedonism

Hedonism is the theory that pleasure is the highest good and the proper aim of human life. In utilitarianism, as discussed in the video, hedonism is used to determine what is good for an individual—maximizing pleasure and minimizing pain. The video script uses hedonism to explain how utilitarianism evaluates the goodness of a situation for an individual.

💡Counterexample

A counterexample is a specific instance that contradicts a general claim or theory. In the video, McCloskey's Sheriff example serves as a counterexample to utilitarianism, suggesting that the theory leads to morally unacceptable conclusions. The counterexample is used to argue against the validity of utilitarianism by providing a scenario where its principles result in an action most would deem morally wrong.

💡Sheriff Example

The Sheriff example, introduced by H. J. McCloskey, is a hypothetical scenario used to challenge utilitarianism. In the video, it is described as a situation where a sheriff must decide whether to frame an innocent person to prevent riots that would lead to many deaths. This example is central to the critique of utilitarianism presented in the video, as it illustrates the theory's potential to demand morally questionable actions for the sake of overall utility.

💡Moral Intuition

Moral intuition refers to the immediate and instinctive judgment about the moral correctness of an action or situation. The video discusses how McCloskey leverages moral intuitions against utilitarianism, arguing that our intuitive moral responses often conflict with the theory's conclusions. The Sheriff example is used to highlight this conflict, as most people's moral intuitions would reject the idea of framing an innocent person, even for the greater good.

💡Distribution of Pleasure and Pain

The distribution of pleasure and pain refers to how these moral values are spread among individuals within a situation. The video script critiques utilitarianism for not considering the distribution, focusing only on the total sum of pleasure and pain. McCloskey's insight, as mentioned in the video, is that utilitarianism's failure to account for distribution can lead to morally problematic outcomes.

💡Biting the Bullet

Biting the bullet is a philosophical term used to describe accepting an uncomfortable or unpalatable consequence of one's beliefs or theories. In the video, J. J. C. Smart is said to 'bite the bullet' by accepting that, according to utilitarianism, framing an innocent person might be the morally right action in the Sheriff example. This illustrates the willingness to accept difficult implications of one's philosophical stance.

💡Moral Theory

A moral theory is a systematic set of principles intended to guide human conduct. In the video, utilitarianism is the primary moral theory under discussion. The video explores whether utilitarianism, as a moral theory, can provide correct guidance on moral actions by examining its response to the Sheriff example and the moral intuitions it challenges.

Highlights

Introduction to the famous argument against utilitarianism by H. J. McCloskey.

The concept of a counter-example in moral philosophy.

Jay Jay See Smart's defense of utilitarianism against McCloskey's objection.

Utilitarianism defined as the moral theory that prioritizes the greatest total of pleasure over pain.

Consequentialism as a broader moral theory focusing on outcomes.

Aggregation theory's role in utilitarianism, emphasizing the total sum of individual goods.

Hedonism's influence on utilitarianism, focusing on maximizing pleasure and minimizing pain.

The McCloskey's Sheriff example as a challenge to the aggregation aspect of utilitarianism.

The scenario where a sheriff must decide between framing an innocent to prevent riots or allowing many deaths.

Utilitarianism's stance that the sheriff is morally required to frame the innocent to prevent greater harm.

McCloskey's critique that utilitarianism permits morally repugnant actions like framing the innocent.

The philosophical debate on whether a single counter-example can disprove a general moral theory.

Smart's initial response suggesting that utilitarianism might not require the sheriff to frame the innocent due to the risk of being discovered.

McCloskey's rejoinder that the scenario can be adjusted to ensure the sheriff won't be caught framing the innocent.

Smart's ultimate acceptance of the utilitarian conclusion that framing an innocent person is morally right in this scenario.

The philosophical concept of 'biting the bullet' and its application to Smart's defense of utilitarianism.

The challenge posed to students to consider whether framing an innocent person is ever morally right, questioning the validity of utilitarianism.

Transcripts

play00:00

that is his McCluskey's insight he

play00:03

realized that utilitarianism was based

play00:07

on a principle that doesn't care about

play00:12

who gets what consequences this time we

play00:23

are talking about what is probably the

play00:25

most famous argument against

play00:28

utilitarianism that has ever been

play00:31

suggested in the history of moral

play00:33

philosophy and this is a famous argument

play00:36

involving a sheriff it comes originally

play00:40

from the philosopher H Jay McCluskey

play00:49

McCluskey introduced this example and

play00:51

the example is what's called a counter

play00:55

example which is a specific type a

play00:59

counter example is a specific type of

play01:02

objection to a claim or a moral theory

play01:05

we'll come back to exactly what a

play01:07

counter example is I'll say something

play01:09

briefly about that but actually I think

play01:12

I have another video about counter

play01:14

examples if I do then I will link to it

play01:17

somewhere if I don't then I won't but we

play01:21

didn't read anything by H get Jay

play01:24

McCluskey we read for this course

play01:27

something written by Jay Jay see smart

play01:33

smart

play01:34

was a philosopher who lived and worked

play01:38

mostly in Australia in the 20th century

play01:41

I believe he died in 2012 and he was a

play01:45

utilitarian so he was defending

play01:48

utilitarianism but he knew that

play01:51

McCloskey had you know introduced this

play01:55

really famous really powerful objection

play01:58

to utilitarianism and so the portion of

play02:01

smart that we read for today is the

play02:04

portion where he first summarizes

play02:06

McCluskey's Sherriff example and then he

play02:09

responds to that example he responds to

play02:11

the the objection to utilitarian

play02:14

and so we're gonna talk about both of

play02:15

those today first however let's remind

play02:19

ourselves a little bit about

play02:21

utilitarianism right so utilitarianism

play02:25

as we've said before in this course is

play02:28

the moral theory that says that we are

play02:32

required morally required to do whatever

play02:34

action will produce the the outcome with

play02:39

the greatest total of pleasure - pain

play02:41

that's your Tillet Arianism and we saw

play02:44

right that utilitarianism is a version

play02:47

of consequentialism and consequentialism

play02:51

is the sort of more general

play02:54

moral theory that says you have to do

play02:56

whatever is going to produce the best

play02:58

outcome whatever is going to have the

play03:00

best consequences so it's the

play03:02

consequences or outcome outcomes that

play03:04

matter what makes an outcome good well

play03:07

what makes an outcome good according to

play03:10

the utilitarian is answered by another

play03:12

theory that we've been calling

play03:14

aggregation aggregation is the theory

play03:17

that an outcome is good a situation

play03:21

involving lots of people is good if the

play03:24

total or the sum of how good that

play03:27

situation is for individual people is

play03:30

the greatest

play03:30

so aggregation is just the addition

play03:34

theory of the goodness of situations but

play03:38

then well so you figure out what to do

play03:41

based on the consequences says

play03:43

consequentialism and then you figure out

play03:45

how good the consequences are which is

play03:48

the best consequences you figure that

play03:50

out by adding up how good those

play03:52

consequences or those situations are for

play03:54

individual people but then you have the

play03:56

question of well what makes a situation

play03:58

good for individual people and the

play04:01

answer to that according to the

play04:02

utilitarian is hedonism hedonism is the

play04:07

theory that says that a situation is

play04:11

good for an individual person if it

play04:13

maximizes to the degree to which it

play04:15

maximizes their pleasure and minimizes

play04:17

their pain

play04:18

hedonism says that pain is the thing

play04:21

that matters ultimately for people it's

play04:25

the thing that's good for people or

play04:27

sorry pleasure

play04:27

the thing that's good for people and

play04:29

pain is the thing that's bad for people

play04:31

okay so utilitarianism as we've been

play04:34

saying in this course is the combination

play04:35

of these three sub theses notice that

play04:40

this sheriff example that we're going to

play04:43

talk about today summarized by JJC smart

play04:46

originally from HJ McCloskey or whatever

play04:48

this example is going to put pressure on

play04:52

aggregation it's going to put pressure

play04:55

on the idea that what makes a

play04:58

circumstance or a situation good is the

play05:01

total sum of how good it is for all the

play05:04

individual people here in one sentence

play05:06

is the objection to utilitarianism

play05:13

here we go suppose that the sheriff of a

play05:16

small town can prevent serious riots in

play05:19

which hundreds of people will be killed

play05:21

only by framing and executing as a

play05:25

scapegoat an innocent man okay so we

play05:29

understand what the scenario is some

play05:31

crime has been committed some terrible

play05:33

thing has happened and the people are

play05:37

convinced that someone did it they think

play05:40

they know who did it and the sheriff

play05:42

knows that that person is innocent but

play05:46

the sheriff can't convince these

play05:48

agitated citizens and if they don't get

play05:51

what they see as justice they're going

play05:55

to riot and it's just definitely gonna

play05:58

happen that hundreds of people are going

play06:02

to be killed

play06:03

in these riots and so the thought is

play06:07

this is the thought and it's not in this

play06:09

sentence right but the thought is so

play06:12

utilitarianism says that the sheriff

play06:17

must is morally required to frame the

play06:20

innocent person and have the innocent

play06:22

person killed executed even though they

play06:25

did not commit the crime just so that

play06:27

well just so that this riot won't occur

play06:31

in which well indeed hundreds of people

play06:33

would die because utilitarianism says

play06:35

that you have to just do the addition

play06:39

you have to you have to add up all of

play06:41

the pain caused by not framing the

play06:44

innocent man and then consider the

play06:47

alternative add up all the pain and

play06:49

pleasure that will result from framing

play06:52

the innocent man and it's just obvious

play06:53

that framing this person is the better

play06:56

outcome when it comes to the sum of pain

play07:00

and pleasure

play07:01

so utilitarianism says that the sheriff

play07:03

has to frame an innocent person but the

play07:07

thought goes McCluskey's thought the

play07:10

thought is but that's awful framing an

play07:14

innocent person is a terrible terrible

play07:16

thing and so if utilitarianism gets this

play07:21

result well then it's not the right

play07:24

moral theory

play07:26

it's a moral theory that's supposed to

play07:27

tell us which actions are right and

play07:29

which actions are wrong but it tells us

play07:31

that this profoundly wrong action is

play07:34

right so it's the wrong theory that's

play07:38

the sense in which this is a putative

play07:41

counter example it's an example that

play07:44

goes counter to the generalization right

play07:46

utilitarianism is a theory and it's

play07:48

basically just a generalization it says

play07:50

all the actions like this are good and

play07:52

all the actions like that are bad and so

play07:54

when you have a general statement like

play07:56

that you can disprove a general

play07:58

statement like that with a single

play08:00

example a single example that goes

play08:02

counter to that general statement right

play08:05

if you can find a single example of some

play08:08

action that utilitarianism says is good

play08:12

but is actually bad like this then

play08:15

you've proven that utilitarianism isn't

play08:18

correct it isn't true it isn't a true

play08:20

generalization about which actions are

play08:22

good and which actions are bad that's

play08:24

the sense in which it's a counter

play08:26

example the counter example is just one

play08:28

type of objection to a philosophical

play08:31

theory or to any general claim that's

play08:34

the objection if you've understood

play08:37

what's going on then you should feel the

play08:40

force of this objection you should think

play08:42

Oh utilitarianism is in trouble it's in

play08:46

desperate trouble this is bad because

play08:49

you should think Oh God framing an

play08:52

innocent person is terrible and so any

play08:55

moral theory that says it's good is just

play08:59

out of whack

play09:00

it gets the wrong result in this case

play09:03

notice also that the problem is

play09:08

fundamentally a problem with the

play09:10

aggregation portion of utilitarianism

play09:15

aggregation just says that if you want

play09:17

to know how good a situation or an

play09:19

outcome is then you just do addition

play09:23

two plus six equals eight you get get

play09:28

that same result as if you did four plus

play09:31

four that also equals eight here's the

play09:34

thing about addition addition doesn't

play09:37

care about the distribution of things

play09:40

you still get the same number eight even

play09:43

if you have more over here than you have

play09:45

over here right

play09:46

you still get eight if you divide them

play09:49

equally evenly

play09:50

you still get eight aggregation as a

play09:54

theory about what makes a situation good

play09:56

for people it doesn't care about the

play09:58

distribution of pleasure and pain it

play10:01

just cares about the total it just cares

play10:03

about the sum so utilitarianism doesn't

play10:08

care if someone is innocent for a crime

play10:11

of a crime punishing them might be the

play10:14

right thing to do even if they are

play10:15

innocent so long as punishing them will

play10:18

result in the most pleasure in the least

play10:20

pain that is his McCluskey's insight he

play10:25

realized that utilitarianism was based

play10:28

on a principle that doesn't care about

play10:33

who gets what consequences and so he's

play10:36

trying to put pressure on that theory by

play10:39

leveraging the fact that we have a moral

play10:41

intuition that it does matter who did

play10:43

what right it does matter what

play10:46

consequences you get based on your own

play10:48

actions

play10:49

so he's leveraging that fact to attack

play10:51

utilitarianism and show that it's an

play10:53

incorrect flawed moral theory okay

play10:58

that's the objection that's the counter

play11:01

example that's the main thing I wanted

play11:04

to get through you know in this lecture

play11:06

or whatever but it's worth talking about

play11:09

smarts response okay so here's what

play11:13

smart says initially smart points out

play11:15

that you know a utilitarian could

play11:18

respond to this example and say well

play11:20

look actually utilitarianism gets the

play11:23

result that you know the sheriff

play11:27

shouldn't punish the innocent man

play11:30

shouldn't frame the innocent person

play11:31

right and have them executed because you

play11:34

know when you frame someone there's

play11:35

always a big risk

play11:37

a significant risk that you're going to

play11:39

be found out and if you're found out

play11:40

then that's going to undermine the faith

play11:43

that the people in the society have in

play11:46

the justice system and when you

play11:48

undermine their you know their faith in

play11:51

the justice system

play11:52

terrible terrible consequences result

play11:54

much worse even than the riot and so the

play11:59

thought is utilitarianism gets the right

play12:01

result that's a first utilitarianism

play12:03

response that smart notices but smart

play12:06

admits that McCluskey has a rejoinder he

play12:09

has a reply to that which is just this

play12:12

you can keep tweaking the scenario right

play12:16

you can add the fact that the sheriff is

play12:18

very good at framing people knows about

play12:21

himself that he's very good at framing

play12:23

people he knows that he'll get away with

play12:25

it

play12:26

he's trying to do the morally right

play12:27

thing but he knows he can pull off

play12:30

framing someone and not get caught what

play12:34

if he knows that right if he knows that

play12:36

then we have a new situation a new

play12:39

scenario and it seems to function as a

play12:42

counter example to utilitarianism so

play12:44

smart just ends up admitting that yes

play12:47

utilitarianism the moral theory gets the

play12:50

result in some situations like this that

play12:53

the morally required thing the morally

play12:56

right thing is to frame an innocent

play12:57

person and smarts ultimate response to

play13:00

this as a utilitarian is just to say yes

play13:04

you're right but that's the right answer

play13:06

framing the innocent man is actually the

play13:09

morally right thing to do that's what

play13:12

smart says and he argues for this just

play13:15

by emphasizing how serious these riots

play13:19

might be how bad they are remember in

play13:23

the riots smart says people will die and

play13:27

those people are innocent too

play13:30

it's not an easy choice for the sheriff

play13:33

but at the end of the day smart says

play13:35

although it's it's it's uncomfortable to

play13:38

frame an innocent person for a crime

play13:42

it's actually the right thing to do

play13:44

because hundreds of people hundreds

play13:47

hundreds much more than the one innocent

play13:50

person

play13:50

that just needs to be framed and

play13:52

executed right hundreds of innocent

play13:54

people will die and so smart just as we

play13:57

say in in you know in philosophy smart

play14:00

just bites the bullet biting a bullet is

play14:03

something that you do when you have to

play14:04

undergo some very painful surgery right

play14:09

in order to weather the pain you you

play14:11

bite on a bullet well smart just bites

play14:15

the bullet he has to take the pain of

play14:18

admitting that framing an innocent

play14:20

person is the right thing to do

play14:21

the question of course that you should

play14:23

be asking yourself is whether that's

play14:26

right

play14:26

whether framing the innocent person in

play14:28

this situation is the morally right

play14:30

thing to do if it is then utilitarianism

play14:34

seems like a plausible moral theory if

play14:38

framing an innocent person is never the

play14:40

right thing to do then you must think

play14:44

that utilitarianism is false

play14:54

you

Rate This

5.0 / 5 (0 votes)

Étiquettes Connexes
UtilitarianismEthical DilemmaMcCluskeySheriff ExampleMoral PhilosophyH. J. McCloskeyJ. J. C. SmartConsequentialismHedonismMoral Theory
Besoin d'un résumé en anglais ?