Public Health Ethics. Thinking about bioethics, human rights, justice and moral responsibility

Global Health with Greg Martin
13 Oct 202129:19

Summary

TLDRThis video script delves into the multifaceted realm of public health ethics, categorizing ethical considerations into four domains: individual, group, national, and global perspectives. It explores principles like bioethics, human rights, and the philosophical debates between deontological and utilitarian ethics. The script also examines distributive justice, inequality, and inequity, advocating for the least well-off in society. Finally, it challenges viewers to confront moral responsibility and the concept of moral distance in a global context.

Takeaways

  • πŸ“š Ethics in public health is guided by a framework that categorizes ethical considerations into four buckets: individuals, groups, nation-states, and global civil society.
  • 🧩 Bioethics, applicable to individuals, is based on four principles: beneficence, non-maleficence, autonomy, and justice, which are crucial in medical and public health contexts.
  • 🌟 Human rights encompass both civil and political rights for individuals and economic, social, and cultural rights for groups, highlighting the importance of rights in health equity.
  • πŸ€” Deontological ethics, based on absolute rights and wrongs, contrasts with utilitarian ethics, which focuses on maximizing happiness or utility for the greatest number, often used in public health decision-making.
  • πŸ” The concept of 'moral responsibility' at a global level prompts reflection on our duty to address historic injustices and their impact on current global health disparities.
  • 🌐 'Moral distance' challenges the notion that physical or emotional distance from a situation lessens our moral obligation to act, a concept relevant to global health initiatives.
  • πŸ› Distributive justice, a concept by John Rawls, suggests that a just society is one where inequality is arranged to ensure the best possible situation for the least advantaged members of society.
  • πŸ”„ The difference between 'inequality' and 'inequity' is significant, with the former being a neutral term and the latter indicating systematic unfairness that leads to health disparities.
  • πŸ›‘ The 'trolley problem' thought experiment illustrates the complexity of ethical decision-making, showing how our moral judgments can change based on the framing of a scenario.
  • πŸ›οΈ The example of sacrificing a pair of shoes to save a child's life is used to discuss moral responsibility in the context of global poverty and the need for affluent societies to contribute to global health.
  • 🌱 The video emphasizes the importance of understanding and advocating for ethical principles in public health, including the need for nuanced discussions on ethical dilemmas.

Q & A

  • What are the four buckets of ethical tools mentioned in the framework for public health?

    -The four buckets of ethical tools mentioned are: considerations for individuals, groups of people, the nation-state, and global civil society.

  • What does the term 'bioethics' refer to in the context of public health?

    -Bioethics refers to the set of principles that guide ethical decision-making in medical and public health contexts, including beneficence, non-maleficence, autonomy, and justice.

  • What are the two types of human rights discussed in the script, and how do they differ?

    -The two types of human rights are civil and political rights, which apply to individuals, and economic, social, and cultural rights, which apply to groups of people.

  • What is the difference between deontological ethics and utilitarian ethics?

    -Deontological ethics, based on Immanuel Kant's philosophy, asserts that there are absolute rights and wrongs, while utilitarian ethics, developed by Jeremy Bentham and John Stuart Mill, focuses on maximizing the overall good or happiness for the most people.

  • What is the thought experiment introduced by Philippa Foote to illustrate the complexities of ethical decision-making?

    -Philippa Foote's thought experiment involves a trolley problem, where individuals must decide between diverting a trolley to kill one person or doing nothing and allowing it to kill five people, highlighting the nuances of deontological and utilitarian ethics.

  • What is the concept of 'distributive justice' in the context of nation-states?

    -Distributive justice refers to the ethical concept of how resources and benefits should be fairly distributed within a society, taking into account issues of inequality and inequity.

  • What is the difference between 'inequality' and 'inequity' as discussed in the script?

    -Inequality refers to an uneven distribution of resources or outcomes across a society, while inequity specifically denotes a systematic unfairness that leads to such inequalities.

  • What is the 'veil of ignorance' thought experiment by John Rawls, and what does it aim to illustrate?

    -The 'veil of ignorance' is a thought experiment where individuals imagine deciding on the principles of justice without knowing their own position in society, aiming to illustrate how much inequality in society should be tolerated.

  • What are the two key concepts to consider when discussing public health ethics at a global level?

    -The two key concepts are moral responsibility, which involves taking responsibility for historical injustices, and moral distance, which challenges the idea that physical distance should affect our moral obligations.

  • What is the example given by Peter Singer in his paper 'Famine, Affluence, and Morality' to illustrate the concept of moral distance?

    -Peter Singer uses the example of choosing between saving a drowning child at the cost of ruining an expensive pair of shoes versus donating the money equivalent to the shoes to save a child's life in a distant country, to illustrate the concept of moral distance.

Outlines

00:00

πŸ” Introduction to Public Health Ethics

The video script begins with an introduction to the concept of public health ethics, emphasizing the importance of ethical decision-making in the field. It outlines a framework for addressing ethical issues, categorizing them into four buckets: individuals, groups, nation-states, and global civil society. The speaker promises to delve into each category, starting with a bird's eye view and then explaining specific concepts such as bioethics, human rights, and utilitarian versus deontological ethics. The goal is to provide viewers with a comprehensive understanding of the ethical considerations relevant to public health professionals.

05:01

🌟 Bioethics and Human Rights in Public Health

This paragraph delves into the principles of bioethics, which are crucial in medical and public health contexts. It introduces four key principles: beneficence, non-maleficence, autonomy, and justice. Beneficence and non-maleficence focus on the balance of risks and benefits in medical interventions, with the aim to do good and avoid harm. Autonomy emphasizes the importance of informed consent, allowing individuals to voluntarily participate in treatments or research. Justice addresses the fair distribution of healthcare resources and the ethical implications of research outcomes, particularly in the context of trials conducted in developing countries.

10:02

πŸ‘₯ Human Rights and Group Ethics in Public Health

The script continues by discussing human rights as they pertain to groups of people, distinguishing between civil and political rights, which are individual freedoms, and economic, social, and cultural rights, which apply to groups and populations. It highlights the importance of these rights in achieving public health goals and the ethical considerations involved in ensuring access to essential services like clean water, housing, education, and healthcare. The paragraph also introduces deontological and utilitarian ethics, setting the stage for a deeper exploration of ethical decision-making within groups.

15:04

πŸ€” Ethical Dilemmas: Deontological vs. Utilitarian Ethics

This section explores the philosophical underpinnings of ethical decision-making, contrasting deontological ethics, which are based on absolute rights and wrongs, with utilitarian ethics, which prioritize the greatest good for the greatest number. The speaker uses the famous trolley problem to illustrate the complexities of these ethical frameworks, showing how the way a problem is presented can influence our moral judgments. The discussion encourages viewers to reflect on the nuances of ethical reasoning and the importance of considering different perspectives.

20:05

πŸ› Distributive Justice and Inequality in Nation-States

The focus shifts to the ethical responsibilities of nation-states, particularly in the realm of distributive justice. The paragraph clarifies the difference between inequality, which is the uneven distribution of resources, and inequity, which results from systematic unfairness. It challenges the viewer to consider the appropriate level of inequality in society, referencing John Rawls' theory of justice and the concept of the 'veil of ignorance' to explore the idea of a just society where the least well-off are as well-off as possible.

25:05

🌐 Global Public Health Ethics: Moral Responsibility and Distance

The final paragraph broadens the ethical discussion to a global scale, introducing the concepts of moral responsibility and moral distance. It prompts reflection on our obligations to address historical injustices and the ethical implications of our actions in a global context. The script references Peter Singer's thought experiment about the moral obligation to help those in need, regardless of geographical distance, and challenges the notion of moral distance as a barrier to fulfilling our ethical duties.

Mindmap

Keywords

πŸ’‘Ethics

Ethics refers to the moral principles that govern a person's or group's behavior. In the context of the video, ethics is the philosophical basis for determining right and wrong in decision-making and actions, especially in public health. The script discusses various ethical frameworks and principles, such as bioethics and human rights, that are crucial for navigating complex public health issues.

πŸ’‘Bioethics

Bioethics is the study of ethical issues arising in the fields of medicine and biology. The script outlines four key principles of bioethics: beneficence, non-maleficence, autonomy, and justice. These principles guide medical professionals and researchers in making ethical decisions that prioritize patient welfare and fairness in healthcare delivery.

πŸ’‘Beneficence

Beneficence is the ethical principle that promotes actions that are in the best interest of the individual, aiming to bring about benefits and prevent harm. The script uses beneficence to discuss the obligation of medical professionals to ensure that patients benefit from their treatments and are not subjected to unnecessary risks.

πŸ’‘Non-maleficence

Non-maleficence is the ethical duty to 'do no harm.' It complements beneficence by emphasizing the avoidance of harm alongside the pursuit of good. The script mentions non-maleficence in the context of medical interventions, where professionals must balance potential benefits against possible harm.

πŸ’‘Autonomy

Autonomy in ethics refers to the capacity and right of individuals to make informed decisions for themselves. The script discusses autonomy as a critical principle in bioethics, highlighting the importance of patient consent and the ability of individuals to choose their medical treatments freely.

πŸ’‘Justice

Justice in the context of bioethics involves the fair distribution of healthcare resources and ensuring equal access to medical services. The script touches on justice in relation to clinical trials and the ethical obligation to distribute benefits and burdens equitably among participants and society.

πŸ’‘Human Rights

Human rights are the fundamental rights to which every individual is entitled. The script distinguishes between civil and political rights, which apply to individuals, and economic, social, and cultural rights, which apply to groups of people. These rights are essential in public health, as they influence policies and actions that affect health outcomes.

πŸ’‘Deontological Ethics

Deontological ethics, rooted in the philosophy of Immanuel Kant, is the approach that certain rights and duties are absolute and should be followed regardless of outcomes. The script uses deontological ethics to explore the concept of inherent moral wrongs, such as the prohibition against killing, even in complex scenarios.

πŸ’‘Utilitarian Ethics

Utilitarian ethics, associated with Jeremy Bentham and John Stuart Mill, focuses on maximizing overall happiness or utility. The script contrasts this with deontological ethics, using thought experiments to illustrate the challenges of deciding what is ethically right based on outcomes versus adherence to moral rules.

πŸ’‘Distributive Justice

Distributive justice is a principle of fairness in the distribution of resources within a society. The script references John Rawls' theory of justice, which posits that a just society is one where inequality is allowed only to the extent that it improves the situation of the least advantaged members of society.

πŸ’‘Moral Responsibility

Moral responsibility refers to the obligation to take responsibility for one's actions, especially in the context of historical injustices. The script prompts viewers to consider the extent to which individuals and societies should be held accountable for past wrongs and their present-day implications.

πŸ’‘Moral Distance

Moral distance is the concept that the physical or emotional distance from a moral dilemma should not affect one's sense of responsibility. The script uses Peter Singer's thought experiment to challenge the notion that we can ignore the suffering of distant others simply because we are not directly confronted with it.

Highlights

Ethics is a framework for decision-making in public health, categorized into four buckets: individuals, groups, nation-states, and global civil society.

Bioethics includes four principles: beneficence, non-maleficence, autonomy, and justice, which are crucial for medical and public health professionals.

Human rights encompass both civil and political rights for individuals, and economic, social, and cultural rights for groups, affecting public health policies.

Deontological ethics, based on Immanuel Kant's philosophy, asserts absolute rights and wrongs, in contrast to utilitarian ethics which focuses on outcomes.

Utilitarian ethics, developed by Jeremy Bentham and John Stuart Mill, emphasizes maximizing happiness or utility for the greatest number of people.

The trolley problem illustrates the complexity of ethical decisions, showing how framing affects moral judgments in deontological vs. utilitarian terms.

Inequality is the uneven distribution of resources, whereas inequity is systematic unfairness leading to such disparities, with different implications for public health.

Distributive justice, as discussed by John Rawls, involves tolerating inequality only to the extent that it benefits the least advantaged in society.

Global public health ethics considers moral responsibility for historical injustices and the concept of moral distance in assisting those in need worldwide.

Peter Singer's thought experiment challenges the notion of moral distance, arguing that our responsibility to help should not be diminished by physical distance.

Ethical considerations in public health require a nuanced understanding of individual rights, group dynamics, national policies, and global responsibilities.

The importance of advocating for good policies based on a deep understanding of distributive justice and equity for public health professionals.

The necessity for public health professionals to balance immediate enforceability of rights with long-term aspirational goals for groups.

The ethical dilemma of autonomy in medical interventions, where patient consent is paramount unless capacity is compromised.

The role of ethical considerations in the aftermath of clinical trials, ensuring participants receive fair benefits from research outcomes.

The philosophical debate between deontological and utilitarian ethics is crucial for making decisions regarding groups in public health.

The significance of understanding both inequality and inequity to effectively address health disparities from a public health perspective.

Transcripts

play00:00

today we're talking about public health

play00:02

ethics

play00:20

ethics is the philosophy around how it

play00:22

is that we should live what is right in

play00:24

terms of the decisions and actions that

play00:25

we take there are a lot of tools that

play00:27

can be used to think through ethical

play00:29

issues and ethical problems i put those

play00:31

tools into four buckets right and this

play00:34

is a framework that i've developed that

play00:35

i found quite useful in my career in

play00:37

public health to think through ethical

play00:38

problems right so we've got to think

play00:40

through ethical problems with respect to

play00:42

individuals groups of people the nation

play00:44

state and the responsibilities of the

play00:46

nation state and of course global civil

play00:48

society okay i hope you find this useful

play00:53

okay so this is the overall framework

play00:55

this is the in a nutshell this is the

play00:56

bird's eye view in this framework you

play00:58

can see a couple of words and ideas that

play00:59

you might not be familiar with don't

play01:01

worry don't panic we're going to go into

play01:02

each of these things individually one at

play01:04

a time and i'm going to explain each of

play01:05

them quite carefully to you just so that

play01:08

we can just quickly go through the the

play01:09

overall

play01:10

idea with respect to individuals we're

play01:12

going to talk about bioethics i'm going

play01:14

to explain what is meant by bioethics

play01:15

and the principles around bioethics

play01:17

we're going to talk about human rights

play01:18

now human rights

play01:20

applies both to the individual

play01:22

but also to groups of people and they're

play01:24

applying different ways right so there

play01:26

are human rights called civil and

play01:27

political rights and they apply to

play01:29

individuals and there are human rights

play01:31

called economic social and cultural

play01:33

rights and they apply to groups of

play01:35

people so that's why that the idea of

play01:36

human rights spans both of these buckets

play01:38

right in the groups of people buckets

play01:40

we've got this idea of deontological and

play01:43

utilitarian ethics right and that's a

play01:46

really really interesting conversation

play01:48

about what is right in terms of deciding

play01:51

what to do with groups of people

play01:52

extremely important in the context of

play01:54

public health so we really want to pay

play01:56

attention and focus on that part of the

play01:58

conversation then with respect to

play02:00

countries we want to understand how it

play02:01

is that nation states and governments in

play02:04

nation states should make decisions

play02:06

about the people within the nation

play02:07

states especially this idea of

play02:09

distributive justice who has what how

play02:12

much inequality and inequity is

play02:14

permissible in the context of a country

play02:17

right and we're going to distinguish

play02:19

between the idea of inequality and

play02:20

inequity so these are ideas and we're

play02:22

going to tease that out during the talk

play02:24

and that's super interesting and i know

play02:26

a lot of you might think well i'm not

play02:27

part of the government so why does that

play02:28

matter to me as public health

play02:30

professionals we need to advocate for

play02:32

good policies so understanding the

play02:34

arguments that underpin distributive

play02:36

justice extremely important for public

play02:38

health professionals

play02:39

and then finally we all form part of a

play02:42

global community global civil society

play02:44

and there are some ideas and they fall

play02:47

under two ideas that i've kind of got to

play02:49

understand and enjoy thinking about one

play02:51

is moral responsibility and that other

play02:53

is moral distance so we're going to talk

play02:55

about all of these things one at a time

play02:56

thanks for watching until now stick with

play02:59

me if you're feeling a bit confused

play03:00

don't worry everything will be clear

play03:02

very soon okay so hang in there

play03:06

[Music]

play03:08

when we think about what is right and

play03:09

what is wrong with respect to

play03:10

individuals right we've got this idea of

play03:12

bioethics and bioethics is something

play03:14

that applies obviously in the medical

play03:15

profession more broadly it's not just a

play03:17

public health issue but of course it

play03:19

does apply in public health it's also

play03:20

something that's used in medical

play03:22

research and by biomedical research a

play03:24

lot okay in terms of clinical trials et

play03:26

cetera et cetera so what do we mean when

play03:28

we talk about bioethics firstly we're

play03:30

talking about these four principles that

play03:32

we've all agreed to in the medical world

play03:34

that we think these are what we think

play03:35

are important some people add to this

play03:37

this list isn't a definitive list but

play03:39

these are the four most commonly ones

play03:40

that are talked about

play03:42

right these are terms you may not have

play03:43

heard before beneficence non-mulphy

play03:44

non-malfeasance autonomy and justice

play03:46

beneficence is really the idea that we

play03:48

should be in the first instance doing

play03:50

what we think is in the best interest of

play03:51

the person in front of us right so they

play03:53

should benefit from whatever it is that

play03:55

they're participating in and the

play03:58

non-malfeasance is almost the other side

play03:59

of the same coin we should not be doing

play04:01

something or taking an action that we

play04:02

believe or we know we even expect to not

play04:06

be in that person's interest to do them

play04:08

harm now where this is a little bit

play04:10

tricky is of course with any medical

play04:11

intervention there are always inherently

play04:13

a certain risks that we need to take

play04:15

into account

play04:17

but when we think about the balance of

play04:18

the risks and benefits we should draw

play04:21

the conclusion that we think that this

play04:22

person will benefit from it and we do

play04:24

not believe that it's likely that they

play04:26

will be harmed by our action

play04:27

notwithstanding the fact that of course

play04:30

things can go awry and with any medical

play04:32

or public health intervention there is

play04:34

always an element of risk

play04:36

which brings us really to the next at

play04:38

the next bullet point here which is

play04:39

autonomy the person needs to be able to

play04:42

engage with whatever treatment with it

play04:44

whatever intervention that we're

play04:45

applying

play04:46

of their own volition right they need to

play04:49

have the capacity to make a decision and

play04:51

they need to have the autonomy to say

play04:54

yes or no to that particular

play04:56

intervention and if they don't want to

play04:58

participate they should be given the

play04:59

freedom not to now there are exceptions

play05:01

to that there are times when people

play05:02

don't have what we call capacity right

play05:04

there might be severe mental illness or

play05:06

neurological decline in which a person

play05:09

isn't able to take a decision on their

play05:10

own behalf and under those circumstances

play05:13

their capacity to make a decision is

play05:14

something that is clinically evaluated

play05:16

there are very definitive criteria that

play05:18

get get applied in those circumstances

play05:20

and making a decision on behalf of

play05:22

someone isn't taken lightly it's it's a

play05:24

very serious thing and there are ways of

play05:26

doing that but that you know but for the

play05:28

most part for most people we want to

play05:29

make sure that they have autonomy and

play05:31

they can decide or decide to or not to

play05:33

participate in whatever it is that we're

play05:35

wanting to apply okay stop the video

play05:37

we're going to go back to talking about

play05:38

ethics in just one minute i just want to

play05:40

quickly say a big thank you to the

play05:42

university of limerick for providing

play05:44

support to create this video

play05:46

one of the things that i absolutely love

play05:48

about the university of limerick's

play05:49

public health program is that there's an

play05:51

emphasis on making sure that they are

play05:52

preparing you for the workplace in other

play05:54

words they are not just teaching you the

play05:56

theory of course you're learning all of

play05:58

the public health theory but they're

play06:00

teaching you that theory in the context

play06:02

of making sure that you are following

play06:04

your graduation really able to make a

play06:06

real contribution in the public health

play06:08

space

play06:09

so if you're thinking of studying public

play06:10

health take a look at the university of

play06:12

limerick highly recommend it i think

play06:13

you'll love it okay let's carry on

play06:15

talking about public health ethics

play06:18

and the final thing is justice we want

play06:20

to make sure that there's no unfairness

play06:22

that's being applied in other words the

play06:23

treatment that we're applying isn't

play06:25

somehow being applied people aren't

play06:26

being given access to it as a function

play06:29

of their gender or the ethnicity or the

play06:32

or some other reason we want to believe

play06:35

that there's an element of justice we

play06:36

also want to believe that where people

play06:38

have for example participated in a trial

play06:40

that they also benefit from the from the

play06:43

outcomes of the research of that trial

play06:45

okay and that's actually something

play06:46

that's become extremely important with

play06:48

respect to hiv trials that we've done in

play06:50

africa where there were people whom

play06:52

if following the trial the treatment

play06:55

that they had

play06:57

spent their risk themselves in a lot of

play06:59

ways to prove worked was not made

play07:01

available to them that would have been

play07:02

considered to be a big injustice in

play07:04

actual fact with respect to hiv trials

play07:06

in africa with antiretroviral drugs for

play07:08

the most part those people were given

play07:10

antiretrovirals for life even subsequent

play07:13

to the ending of the trial which i think

play07:14

was a real boon and demonstrated a real

play07:17

understanding of this notion of justice

play07:18

okay so that's bioethics i'm not going

play07:20

to carry on about that because really

play07:22

there's so much more we need to talk

play07:23

about the next thing we're going to talk

play07:24

about is human rights now there's two

play07:26

types of human rights have alluded to

play07:27

that fact

play07:28

and when we're talking about the

play07:30

individual we really want to talk about

play07:32

what's called civil and political human

play07:33

rights and these are rights that are

play07:35

applied to individuals these are like

play07:37

their freedom to vote freedom to

play07:39

assemble the right to be free from being

play07:42

tortured

play07:43

these are things that as an individual i

play07:45

can request that that right be protected

play07:49

right i can ask that right be enforced

play07:51

and i can ask for it to be enforced now

play07:54

i can today ask that i not be tortured i

play07:56

can today ask that i have the right to

play07:59

be able to vote and the reason i'm

play08:01

making a big deal about the immediacy of

play08:03

the enforcement of that right is because

play08:06

it stands in juxtaposition to the other

play08:08

kind of right we're going to talk about

play08:09

just now which can't be enforced in any

play08:12

immediacy right so civil and political

play08:14

rights these are individual freedoms and

play08:16

of course we believe that they're

play08:17

enforceable they should be enforceable

play08:19

they aren't always enforced we agree as

play08:22

a global civil society that these are

play08:23

important and that they should be

play08:25

enforced and we bestow this right on one

play08:27

another in other words we agree

play08:28

collectively to protect

play08:31

each other's rights to access these

play08:33

freedoms and of course all of this has

play08:35

implications for health right if i'm

play08:36

tortured that's

play08:38

that's bad for my health if i don't have

play08:40

the right to participate in civil

play08:42

society and vote and assemble i don't

play08:44

have any agency then to have decisions

play08:47

about how society is managed that might

play08:49

affect my health i can't influence that

play08:50

i can't advocate for my own health

play08:52

environment so these all have

play08:55

implications for health okay

play08:57

we're going to now talk about groups of

play08:59

people and i'm going to start off that

play09:00

conversation just by continuing to talk

play09:02

about human rights and the aspect of

play09:05

human rights that pertains to groups of

play09:06

people and then we're going to get into

play09:07

the deontological and utilitarian ethics

play09:09

which is super duper interesting so

play09:11

stick with me for that

play09:12

when we're talking about public health

play09:14

effects for groups of people again we

play09:16

want to talk about human rights but this

play09:17

time we're talking about economic social

play09:19

and cultural rights right for

play09:21

individuals it was civil and political

play09:22

rights those were the freedoms of

play09:23

individuals these are rights of groups

play09:26

and of populations

play09:27

now these are rights like the right to

play09:29

access clean water the right to housing

play09:31

the right to education the right to the

play09:33

highest attainable standard of health

play09:35

notice that it's not the right to health

play09:37

but it's the right to the highest

play09:38

attainable standard of health and that

play09:40

there's an important difference there

play09:42

now obviously these things cannot be

play09:44

enforced remember we said the civil and

play09:47

political human rights are things that

play09:48

you could enforce now in the immediate

play09:50

effect you could have those rights

play09:52

respected those freedoms could be

play09:54

attained things like access to fresh

play09:56

water education housing the right to the

play09:58

highest attainable standard of health

play10:00

these are things that that take time to

play10:02

be put in place they're aspirational

play10:04

they're normative these are things that

play10:05

we work toward that we need to invest in

play10:07

and we and we kind of wanted to get to

play10:10

right so they can't be enforced in the

play10:12

immediate effect but there are things

play10:13

that we believe that people should have

play10:15

or at least most places around the world

play10:17

most countries and most governments

play10:18

believe in these economic social and

play10:20

cultural rights so they're very

play10:22

important they're aspirational they're

play10:23

four groups they have certainly have

play10:25

public health implications next we're

play10:27

going to talk about deontological

play10:29

utilitarian ethics this is maybe the

play10:32

most important concept that you to get

play10:34

your head around and i'm going to

play10:36

just create a new board to talk about

play10:38

them because there's some interesting

play10:39

thought experiments that you can use to

play10:41

to really better understand

play10:43

the nuances of deontological and

play10:45

utilitarian ethics

play10:48

okay deontological and utilitarian

play10:50

ethics these are two important concepts

play10:52

and you're really going to enjoy this

play10:53

it's super interesting right

play10:54

genetological ethics were developed by

play10:56

immanuel kant and essentially the idea

play10:58

there was that there are absolute rights

play11:00

and wrongs there are things that are

play11:01

wrong things that are wrong things that

play11:03

are wrong

play11:04

simply because we know that inherently

play11:06

morally ethically these things are wrong

play11:08

and they're wrong by definition right so

play11:11

you might say to kill a person is wrong

play11:13

no matter what the circumstances

play11:15

it's always wrong to kill a human being

play11:17

utilitarian ethics developed by jeremy

play11:19

bentham and and john strutmills

play11:22

said actually no

play11:24

what matters is the outcome of your

play11:27

actions you really want to do the thing

play11:28

that translates into the most good for

play11:30

the most people or you know sometimes it

play11:33

was framed as the most happiness for the

play11:34

most people but really you're trying to

play11:36

maximize the utility of humanity or of

play11:39

group of people and that's what defines

play11:41

what is right and what is wrong now

play11:44

interestingly when people are confronted

play11:46

with these two ideas for the most part

play11:49

most people

play11:51

immediately put themselves into one or

play11:53

other bucket most people sort of have a

play11:55

knee-jerk reaction and feel as if they

play11:57

uh resonate with either uh jeremy

play12:00

bentham or immanuel kant and they they

play12:03

find themselves in one or other camp

play12:06

along came somebody by the name of

play12:07

philippa foote

play12:08

and she said look it's not quite that

play12:10

straightforward and she developed a

play12:12

thought experiment

play12:14

to try and highlight how difficult it is

play12:16

to really distinguish right and wrong

play12:18

with respect to these two different

play12:20

frameworks and the thought experiment

play12:22

went along the lines along i want you to

play12:24

do this with me use your imagination and

play12:27

do this thought experiment and you'll

play12:28

see exactly what i mean

play12:30

right so she said look imagine a tram or

play12:32

trolley and in this case you'll see i've

play12:34

drawn a little train it's not a very

play12:36

good drawing but you know it's the best

play12:37

i could do and it's going along a track

play12:39

and

play12:40

it's heading

play12:41

on the track it's natural courses to go

play12:43

down this way and some evil villain has

play12:46

tied

play12:47

five people to the track

play12:50

and if it goes down that track the train

play12:52

or the tram or the trolley is going to

play12:53

kill all five people for sure they they

play12:56

will not survive

play12:57

interestingly you're standing a little

play13:00

ways off you're in the little hut that

play13:02

the

play13:03

train people stand in and you've got a

play13:04

lever that you can pull and if you pull

play13:05

that lever the train will be diverted

play13:08

onto an alternative track and on this

play13:10

alternative track of course uh what's

play13:12

going to happen is there's just one

play13:13

person tied to the alternative track and

play13:16

that person will get hit by the train

play13:17

and they'll die but you'll have saved

play13:19

the five people and so the first

play13:21

question that philippa foot asked is

play13:23

would you pull the lever

play13:25

and save the five people

play13:27

knowing of course that there'd be one

play13:28

person that still did die when asked and

play13:31

you might find this yourself as you

play13:33

listen to me

play13:34

most people respond they would pull the

play13:37

lever and make that decision

play13:39

now interestingly that is a utilitarian

play13:42

decision right it's maximizing the

play13:45

utility of this particular set of

play13:46

circumstances it is killing a person so

play13:49

it's doing something that would would

play13:50

consider to be deontologically wrong

play13:53

but it is we're maximizing utility but

play13:55

then she said let's take this experiment

play13:57

a step further

play13:58

and let's imagine that you now don't

play14:00

have a lever but instead you've got a

play14:01

footbridge

play14:03

and i would try and draw the footbridge

play14:04

for you but i really you know the train

play14:06

is the best i could do in terms of

play14:07

drawing i wouldn't get this right but

play14:09

you've got a foot bridge that's going

play14:10

over the track

play14:12

you do not have a lever to pull but

play14:14

you've got a footbridge and on that

play14:15

footbridge

play14:16

there's a

play14:18

and you could push the off the

play14:19

footbridge onto the track and that

play14:21

footbridge that tram would would you

play14:23

would push him he would fall off

play14:25

and he'd land on the track and die

play14:28

and he'd be hit by the train but he

play14:29

would stop the train

play14:31

and of course the the five people would

play14:33

be saved

play14:35

so the question is would you

play14:37

climb onto that footbridge and kill the

play14:40

push him off the edge and

play14:43

when the problem is framed like that

play14:44

most people overwhelmingly

play14:46

the vast majority of people said they

play14:48

wouldn't do that they couldn't do that

play14:51

now strictly speaking those two

play14:52

scenarios are from an ethics and moral

play14:55

point of view the exact same thing right

play14:58

you're sacrificing one person to save

play15:01

five

play15:02

but the problem is it's framed in a

play15:04

different way and our brain processes

play15:06

that information in different ways when

play15:07

you're pulling the lever the part of

play15:09

your brain

play15:10

that

play15:11

considers the ethical dilemma simply

play15:13

makes a calculation it's a sort of

play15:15

prefrontal cortex it just sort of says

play15:16

five is more than one that's the better

play15:18

option let's save the five when you're

play15:20

thinking and imagining yourself on a

play15:22

footbridge

play15:23

actually getting up close and personal

play15:25

and killing a person suddenly your

play15:28

emotional centers are evoked and you

play15:30

make that ethical decision in a

play15:32

different part of your brain and under

play15:34

both circumstances you are quite sure

play15:36

that you're making the right decision

play15:38

and most people will swap and then of

play15:40

course the trolley experiments can get

play15:42

changed in multiple ways

play15:45

you could say well on the footbridge the

play15:47

person that you're going to push off the

play15:48

footbridge and they're going to die

play15:50

to save the five isn't a but

play15:51

rather it's the evil villain that tied

play15:53

the five people there in the first place

play15:55

and then suddenly people are like oh

play15:56

hang on hold the phone we don't mind

play15:58

killing him or her

play15:59

let's you know that's fine that's

play16:01

justifiable so there are multiple

play16:04

versions and iterations there's versions

play16:06

of the trolley experiment where the

play16:07

track loops back on itself and it gets

play16:09

more and more complicated but the point

play16:10

is every iteration of this thought

play16:12

experiment demonstrates to us

play16:15

that what we think is right and wrong is

play16:18

for the most part a function of how it

play16:20

is that the problem is framed and we

play16:22

need to think about that we need to keep

play16:24

that in mind very carefully when we get

play16:26

into debates with people about moral and

play16:28

ethical public health problems and not

play16:31

fall into the trap of simply believing a

play16:33

particular paradigm because it's framed

play16:35

in a way or is just sort of too sort of

play16:37

too much on the side of a pure

play16:38

calculation it doesn't take the humanity

play16:40

of the situation into account we have to

play16:42

be more nuanced than that now

play16:45

what does this mean

play16:46

have i taken away two two tools from you

play16:49

or have i given you two tools that you

play16:50

can use i don't know uh all i know is we

play16:53

can't go into these conversations

play16:54

without having that introspective nuance

play16:56

that ability to kind of really reflect

play16:58

on our own position critically and make

play17:01

sure that when we go into an argument

play17:02

about ethics that we're aware that

play17:04

there's often another side to the story

play17:06

which may be quite compelling depending

play17:08

on how it is that that story is being

play17:09

read

play17:10

okay so we've talked about the

play17:11

individual level we've talked about

play17:12

groups of people now we're going to talk

play17:13

about the nation-state countries how it

play17:15

is that countries and governments should

play17:17

apply the ideas of ethics public health

play17:19

ethics and decisions they make

play17:21

specifically with respect to this idea

play17:23

of distributive justice and inequity and

play17:26

inequality

play17:30

okay before we start talking about

play17:31

distributive justice

play17:33

and there's a fantastic paper i'm going

play17:34

to talk about by john rolls i want to

play17:36

talk about the idea of inequality and

play17:38

inequity these two terms get banded

play17:40

about they sometimes get used

play17:41

interchangeably they mean different

play17:43

things and it's really important that we

play17:45

understand them if we're going to really

play17:47

talk about the concept of justice and

play17:49

distributive justice okay so let's just

play17:51

talk firstly about inequality

play17:54

inequality is when there's an uneven

play17:57

distribution of something across social

play17:59

delineations right it could be any

play18:00

delineation it could be gender it could

play18:03

be short people tall people uh irish

play18:05

people south africans any delineation

play18:07

any way of dividing society up when

play18:09

there's an uneven distribution of

play18:10

something across those delineations we

play18:13

call it inequality right now not all

play18:16

inequality is bad so men

play18:19

are taller than women that's not

play18:20

necessarily a bad thing it's just a

play18:22

thing just it happens it's just a fact

play18:24

of the matter uh dutch people are taller

play18:26

than british people

play18:27

again it's not a good thing it's not a

play18:29

bad thing it's just a thing and we just

play18:31

we just live with it there are some

play18:34

inequalities however

play18:36

that exist because of pre-existing

play18:39

unfairness

play18:41

systematic unfairness in society and we

play18:43

call that unfairness inequity so

play18:47

inequity is a systematic unfairness that

play18:49

leads to

play18:50

inequality good example is apartheid

play18:52

south africa had rules and legislation

play18:55

in place

play18:56

that meant that black south africans had

play18:59

economic disadvantages and health

play19:01

disadvantages and whole and educational

play19:03

disadvantages i mean a whole string of

play19:05

freedoms denied to them there was a

play19:08

systematic unfairness in society and

play19:11

that led to inequalities so there was

play19:13

inequity that led to inequalities now

play19:16

importantly when we're talking about

play19:18

health

play19:20

there is a tendency to use this term

play19:22

health inequities which are

play19:24

health inequalities that are a function

play19:26

of an unfairness and and that's a real

play19:28

thing there are

play19:30

unfairnesses that lead to you know there

play19:32

could be economic unfairnesses there

play19:33

could be all sorts of unfairnesses in

play19:35

south africa that have health

play19:36

consequences

play19:38

and there's this term

play19:40

there's this catch-all term called

play19:41

health inequity that people try to use

play19:42

to capture those things the trap that

play19:45

people fall into is believing that those

play19:47

are and only those are the inequalities

play19:50

that we should be addressing and that's

play19:51

not true

play19:53

while it is the case that health

play19:55

inequities these inequalities that are a

play19:57

function of some sort of unfairness have

play19:58

to be addressed at a social level we

play20:00

need to kind of make sure that we live

play20:01

in a fair society

play20:03

that doesn't translate into these sorts

play20:04

of inequalities it's also true that

play20:07

health inequalities

play20:09

that have nothing to do with unfairness

play20:11

if it is possible for us to address them

play20:13

we should

play20:14

okay let me give you an example as a

play20:16

caucasian i'm more likely to develop

play20:18

skin cancer than somebody that's darkly

play20:20

pigmented

play20:21

right that's not an unfairness i'm not

play20:24

being cheated by the world

play20:26

it's just a difference a biological

play20:28

difference between myself and my

play20:30

counterparts that are darker than me

play20:33

should we try and address that as a

play20:35

public health community of course we

play20:36

should be telling people like me to wear

play20:37

sunscreen to stay out of the sun

play20:39

and you know to avoid some of the the

play20:41

risks associated with skin cancer all

play20:44

right so it's not just an inequalities

play20:46

that are a function of unfairness that

play20:48

need to be addressed we need to address

play20:49

any health inequality where we are able

play20:51

to and of course it's true that where

play20:54

there's inequity where there's

play20:55

unfairness absolutely we have to address

play20:57

that that's you know that almost goes

play20:59

without saying but

play21:00

it's also true that it has to be said

play21:02

because we see examples of it all over

play21:03

the world where unfairnesses are not

play21:05

being addressed okay so that's

play21:08

that's inequality and inequity and

play21:10

that's important to understand that

play21:11

because next we're going to talk about

play21:12

this idea of distributive justice and

play21:14

how much inequality in a society should

play21:17

we tolerate

play21:18

okay when we talk about distributive

play21:20

justice there was a paper written by

play21:21

somebody by the name of jonathan rawls

play21:23

and

play21:25

he wrote this paper called theory of

play21:26

justice and it was a very influential

play21:29

paper and it talked about the idea of

play21:31

inequality in society and how much

play21:32

inequality we should tolerate

play21:35

and these are very badly drawn scales

play21:37

down here and i'm going to get back to

play21:38

those in a second but really john rolls

play21:41

came up with a thought experiment and

play21:43

again i want you to do this thought

play21:44

experiment in your mind as as i talk it

play21:47

through imagine yourself in the

play21:48

situation john said okay put yourself

play21:51

behind what he calls the veil of

play21:53

ignorance he calls it the original

play21:55

position

play21:56

it's you remove yourself from your life

play21:59

imagine that you're behind this veil of

play22:00

ignorance and it's called available

play22:02

ignorance because on that you don't know

play22:03

what your life was like on the other

play22:04

side you've been removed from life

play22:06

and the world

play22:08

and you don't remember whether you were

play22:10

black or white whether you were

play22:12

tall short male female a south african

play22:15

or irish you don't know anything about

play22:17

the life that you're going to go back to

play22:19

and you're going to go back to that life

play22:21

now

play22:22

given that you're going to go back to

play22:24

that life

play22:25

and you don't know who you're going to

play22:26

be

play22:27

what level of inequality

play22:30

would you opt for

play22:32

while you're here on on this side of the

play22:34

veil of ignorance what would you

play22:35

consider to be appropriate

play22:38

knowing that in that the world you're

play22:39

going back to could be

play22:42

dramatically unfair with huge

play22:43

inequalities and you could be at the

play22:45

bottom end in fact in the world that

play22:47

we're living at the moment it would be

play22:48

overwhelmingly likely that you would be

play22:51

somewhere in the sort of bottom end you

play22:54

know the sharp end of inequality you

play22:57

know and we do live in a world where a

play22:59

very very few people you know kind of

play23:01

really control the vast majority of the

play23:03

wealth in the world so the question is

play23:05

from behind the veil of ignorance where

play23:06

would you how much inequality would you

play23:08

want in society when you came back it's

play23:11

an interesting question and he came up

play23:13

with a way of thinking about it a way to

play23:15

kind of answer that question because

play23:16

it's you know on the one hand you might

play23:17

say oh no i want to come back to a

play23:18

completely you get an egalitarian world

play23:20

where

play23:21

there's no inequality whatsoever and he

play23:24

argued against that as well by the way

play23:25

and this is where our three little

play23:26

scales come in and here's here's what

play23:28

john rolls kind of suggested he said

play23:30

each of these scales represents sort of

play23:31

a certain level of inequality in society

play23:35

and he was saying look you could have a

play23:36

completely egalitarian society with it

play23:38

everybody has exactly the same amount of

play23:40

absolutely everything and you don't

play23:42

really have any

play23:44

any people that are tremendously poor

play23:46

the other extreme you could have a

play23:48

situation where you have a lot of

play23:50

inequality but it might translate into a

play23:52

tremendously wealthy society but they

play23:53

would in that society be some people who

play23:55

are tremendously poor

play23:57

now john rolls kind of argued that what

play23:59

you you don't really want that either

play24:01

and although to a large extent that is

play24:03

the world that we're currently living in

play24:05

he argued that what you really want is a

play24:06

world where there's

play24:08

some inequality

play24:10

but only inequality in so much as it

play24:13

translates into the least well of

play24:16

being as well off as possible in other

play24:17

words in this scenario because of a

play24:19

little bit of inequality and sometimes a

play24:20

little bit of inequality could spur

play24:22

competition and incentives et cetera et

play24:24

cetera i mean there are reasons why some

play24:26

inequality in the world actually has

play24:28

economic benefit but he said you only

play24:31

want to tolerate as much inequality as

play24:33

translates into the least well-off so

play24:36

the people at sort of this side of

play24:39

the equation being as well off as

play24:41

possible in other words

play24:43

where these people over here

play24:46

are better off than these people over

play24:48

here

play24:49

so if we were to draw a line a dotted

play24:51

line of their level of well-being it's

play24:54

assumed that they're over here where the

play24:56

least well-off in society are the best

play24:58

that they could possibly be

play25:00

that's the level of inequality that we

play25:02

should aspire towards more inequality

play25:05

could lead to the least well of being

play25:07

less well-off than

play25:10

this completely egalitarian situation

play25:12

even if society under those

play25:14

circumstances was a richer society so he

play25:17

was saying let's not go for that let's

play25:18

go for a sort of middle ground with the

play25:20

least well of uh in other words he said

play25:22

the benchmark for what we should

play25:23

tolerate and what we should aspire

play25:25

toward is how well off or how are

play25:28

the least well-off in society that's our

play25:30

barometer those are the people that we

play25:32

need to be concerned about

play25:34

not the overall economy not the wealth

play25:36

of the nation not the gdp per capita not

play25:39

the economic growth rate or none of that

play25:41

how well off are the least well-off in

play25:43

your society that's the measure

play25:45

of whether or not that's the level of

play25:47

inequality that you should tolerate and

play25:49

that's in terms of distributive justice

play25:51

what it is that you should be aspiring

play25:52

towards okay i hope that was useful now

play25:54

we're going to go on to thinking about

play25:56

public health ethics from a global

play25:58

perspective

play25:59

okay so we've talked about the

play26:00

individual we've talked about groups of

play26:01

people we've talked about countries and

play26:02

so obviously the next thing to talk

play26:04

about is at a global level let's talk

play26:06

about moral responsibility and moral

play26:08

distance

play26:12

when we talk about public health ethics

play26:13

at a global level there's two ideas that

play26:15

we need to think about one is moral

play26:17

responsibility and the other is moral

play26:18

distance now i don't have the answers to

play26:21

some of the questions that these ideas

play26:22

pose but i do think that we need to be

play26:23

cognizant of them moral responsibility

play26:26

is the extent to which we need to take

play26:28

responsibility for historic injustices

play26:31

that we have benefited from

play26:33

okay and there's lots of examples of

play26:35

that and the question that needs to be

play26:37

grappled with would be how far back do

play26:39

you go and to what extent do you

play26:41

take moral responsibility for historic

play26:43

injustices and what does that mean how

play26:45

should you respond to that so there's

play26:47

this historic injustice you're going

play26:50

back in time you take moral

play26:51

responsibility for things that happened

play26:52

in the past the other is physical

play26:54

distance and this is this idea of moral

play26:56

distance

play26:57

now peter singer wrote a very

play26:59

influential paper called famine

play27:01

affluence and morality

play27:03

and in it he posed a thought experiment

play27:05

and he said look if you're walking down

play27:06

the road

play27:07

and you pass a child drowning in the mud

play27:11

and you're able to save that child

play27:13

you're just well able to save that child

play27:15

the problem is that if you were to save

play27:17

that child the only way you could do it

play27:19

would be to get your feet stuck in into

play27:21

the mud and there you've just bought a

play27:22

very expensive pair of shoes

play27:24

and those shoes would be ruined

play27:26

i think most of us agree that you

play27:28

shouldn't care too much about the shoes

play27:30

but you should sacrifice the shoes and

play27:32

help the child out of the mud and save

play27:33

the child's life and that's my little

play27:35

diagram here by the way that's a shoe

play27:37

stuck in the mud i know it doesn't look

play27:38

like it i'm not a great artist as you've

play27:40

probably figured out by now

play27:42

now so we all agree save the child

play27:44

sacrifice the shoes none of us have a

play27:46

problem with that

play27:47

but something that peter singer pointed

play27:48

out is that in actual fact we are faced

play27:50

with that exact dilemma all of the time

play27:52

right there are reputable charities out

play27:55

there

play27:56

to which we could give

play27:58

the equivalent of

play28:00

an expensive pair of shoes in full

play28:02

confidence that that might translate

play28:04

into a child's life being saved or

play28:06

perhaps a child being educated or

play28:08

treatment for a child uh to be you know

play28:10

to be treated for some sort of illness

play28:11

but

play28:12

these these are children in africa or in

play28:14

southeast asia and some part of the

play28:16

world where they're

play28:18

so far away from us that it's easy for

play28:20

us to detach ourselves emotionally from

play28:23

their plight

play28:24

and we absolve ourselves of this sense

play28:27

of moral responsibility so peter singer

play28:29

was saying basically the distance

play28:31

shouldn't matter

play28:32

distance isn't an issue there's no such

play28:34

thing as moral distance essentially the

play28:36

responsibility to save a child's life if

play28:38

you're able to

play28:39

should apply

play28:40

regardless of where it is in the world

play28:42

that you are so interesting idea

play28:44

interesting challenge to us all i hope

play28:46

you found this video useful please

play28:48

subscribe to this channel if you haven't

play28:49

already hit the bell notification if you

play28:51

want to get notified of future videos

play28:52

like this you can join the channel as a

play28:55

member that's a slightly different thing

play28:56

and the members of course get access to

play28:58

different videos

play28:59

that's mostly about jobs and careers in

play29:01

the global and public health space

play29:03

i've also got a website called

play29:05

learnmore365.com

play29:07

and i've got lots more teaching material

play29:09

uh there in a lot more detail okay

play29:12

thanks for watching hope you enjoyed

play29:13

this take

play29:15

[Music]

Rate This
β˜…
β˜…
β˜…
β˜…
β˜…

5.0 / 5 (0 votes)

Related Tags
Public HealthEthicsBioethicsHuman RightsUtilitarianismDeontologyDistributive JusticeGlobal SocietyEthical DilemmasHealth Inequity